Project management for small projects second edition Rowe download
Project management for small projects second edition Rowe download
https://ebookname.com/product/project-management-for-small-
projects-second-edition-rowe/
https://ebookname.com/product/strategic-planning-for-project-
management-using-a-project-management-maturity-model-1st-edition-
harold-kerzner/
https://ebookname.com/product/the-project-management-
communications-toolkit-second-edition-carl-l-pritchard/
https://ebookname.com/product/design-methods-and-practices-for-
research-of-project-management-second-edition-beverly-pasian-
rodney-turner/
https://ebookname.com/product/television-studies-the-key-
concepts-routledge-key-guides-1st-edition-bernadette-casey/
Signal and Image Processing in Navigational Systems
Electrical Engineering Applied Signal Processing Series
1st Edition Vyacheslav Tuzlukov
https://ebookname.com/product/signal-and-image-processing-in-
navigational-systems-electrical-engineering-applied-signal-
processing-series-1st-edition-vyacheslav-tuzlukov/
https://ebookname.com/product/armored-units-of-the-russian-civil-
war-white-and-allied-david-bullock/
https://ebookname.com/product/cliffsap-english-literature-and-
composition-2nd-ed-edition-allan-casson/
https://ebookname.com/product/reasons-for-logic-logic-for-
reasons-1st-edition-ulf-hlobil/
https://ebookname.com/product/what-the-nose-knows-the-science-of-
scent-in-everyday-life-first-edition-avery-gilbert/
Basic Vision An Introduction to Visual Perception 2nd
Edition Robert Snowden
https://ebookname.com/product/basic-vision-an-introduction-to-
visual-perception-2nd-edition-robert-snowden/
Project Management
for Small Projects
Second Edition
Sandra F. Rowe, PhD, PMP
8230 Leesburg Pike, Suite 800
Tysons Corner, VA 22182
(703) 790-9595
Fax: (703) 790-1371
www.managementconcepts.com
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or
mechanical, including photocopying, recording, or by an information storage and retrieval system, without permission in
writing from the publisher, except for brief quotations in review articles.
ISBN 978-1-56726-474-6
eISBN 978-1-56726-475-3
About the Author
Sandra Rowe, PhD, PMP, MBA, MSCIS, has more than 25 years of project management
experience. Her responsibilities have included leading information technology and process
improvement projects; developing project management processes, tools, and techniques;
and designing, developing, and delivering project management training programs. She has
also taught graduate-level project management courses.
Dr. Rowe speaks regularly at project management conferences on a variety of topics
related to project management processes, project management for small projects, the
project office, knowledge sharing, and lessons learned.
Dr. Rowe is a member of PMI and received her PMP in 1995. Her educational background
includes a doctor of philosophy in business with a specialization in project management, a
bachelor of science in business, a master’s of business administration, and a master’s of
science in computer and information systems.
To my mother, Minnie Rowe
In memory of my aunts Celia Carruthers,
Mary Johnson, and Ida Booker
Contents
Preface
Acknowledgments
Chapter 9 Controlling
Controlling Process Summary
Controlling Process Activities
Action Items
CONTROLLING PROCESS GUIDE
Chapter 10 Closing
Closing Process Summary
Closing Process Steps
CLOSING PROCESS GUIDE
Glossary
Index
FIGURES
Project
Management
Discipline
CHAPTER
PROJECT OVERVIEW
Projects are a more important part of business now than they ever have been. They exist at
all levels of every organization and must be managed proactively, regardless of size.
Normally when we think of projects, we think of large initiatives such as developing a new
product or service, developing a new information system or enhancing an existing one,
constructing a building, or preparing for a major sports event. Small projects are not
always viewed as projects and therefore are not always treated as projects—especially
smaller, more informal projects, which are often called assignments.
Definition of a Project
As stated in the PMBOK® Guide, Fifth Edition, a project is a temporary endeavor
undertaken to create a unique product, service, or result. A project can create:
• A product that can be a component of another item, an enhanced item, or an end item in
itself
• A service or a capability to perform a service
• A result, such as an outcome or document.
A project has three distinct characteristics.
1. A project is temporary in that it has a beginning and an end. A project always has a
defined start and end date. The project begins with a statement of work or some form
of description of the product, service, or result to be supplied by the project, and it
ends when the objectives are complete or it is determined that the objectives cannot
be met and the project is canceled.
2. A project is unique in that the product, service, or result created as a result of the
project is different in some distinguishing way from all similar products, services, or
results. Unique also indicates that although a project might appear to be similar to
another project because you are producing the same type of deliverable, it really is
not. In both projects you are creating something that did not exist before. Even a
revision to an existing deliverable is considered unique because the revised product
is something that did not exist before.
3. A project is characterized by progressive elaboration. This means the project
develops in steps and grows in detail. Progressive elaboration is continually
improving and detailing a plan as more detailed and specific information and more
accurate estimates become available as the project progresses. When you are first
given a project, you have limited information to work with, usually in the form of a
high-level project description, the project objective, and some assumptions and
constraints. The scope might need to be further defined, and the work activities for the
project need will have to be planned in detail as more specific information becomes
available. Progressive elaboration allows you to manage to a greater amount of detail
as the project evolves.
Another way to view a project is to see a project as something we do one time, as opposed
to operational work, which is continuous and repetitive and is undertaken to sustain the
business. Operational activities have no real completion date; they are ongoing. An
example of a project would be to develop or enhance an accounting system. The
operational activity would be to process biweekly payroll or pay monthly expenses. Both
operational activities and projects are constrained by resources and are planned, executed,
and controlled (Figure 1.1). However, projects, due to their temporary nature, are initiated
and closed.
FIGURE 1.1 Comparison of Projects and Operations
Characteristics Criteria
Characteristics Criteria
Team members Four part-time team members: project manager and three subject
matter experts
Single objective Revise the planning process to include changes made to the
corporate project management process and to be consistent with
the current version of the PMBOK® Guide
Interdependencies None
among skill areas
A small project can also be part of a program. (Refer to Chapter 12 for a discussion on
Projects as Part of a Program.)
Scenario
Kenny is an analyst with ambitions of becoming a project manager. He is aware of the definition of a project and the
importance of using project management on small projects. He has been working on assignments and wonders if he could
be more successful with completing his assignments if he used project management methods and tools. Can project
management be used on an assignment?
The answer is yes. An assignment can be treated as a simple project.
Scenario
Kenny has learned that project management is both an art and a science and has concluded that project managers need to
constantly balance people and processes.
CHAPTER
Planning
Planning is necessary to define and mature the project scope, develop the project
management plan, and identify and schedule the project activities that occur within the
project. It ensures that you request the appropriate amount of time and resources to
complete the work. Planning is a challenge for a project of any size. Getting the right
people together at the right time to discuss the project details can be painful.
Planning for a small project is even more of a challenge. The project is already perceived
as being easy to deliver because of its size. Small equals easy. Because of that perception,
adequate time is not set aside for detailed planning. (Why waste time planning when you
could be creating project deliverables?) The first reaction after receiving the small project
is to jump right in and start performing the project activities without planning. Even the
most experienced project manager has fallen into this trap at least once. By not planning,
you start out thinking the project is small and then end up hoping that the project really is
small. Also, by not planning you may overlook a critical component of the project.
The project manager should always make sure the scope, work effort, and costs are
defined. With a loosely defined scope, the project manager runs the risk of it constantly
changing, and scope creep could become a problem. The project manager should also make
time to plan because the plan provides direction for the project, is a means for control, and
Random documents with unrelated
content Scribd suggests to you:
makes the vote of the State as efficient as it could be if it were
required to be cast as a unit, while the chances for its protection are
increased by the opportunity of gaining single votes from the
delegations of other States.
These and similar considerations ultimately led a large majority of
the States to prefer a union of the plan of an equal number of
senators from each State with that which would allow them to vote
per capita.[163] The number of two was adopted as the most
convenient, under all the circumstances, because most likely to unite
the despatch of business with the constant presence of an equal
number from every State.
With this peculiar character, the outline of the institution went to the
committee of detail. On the consideration of their report, these
provisions, as we have seen, became complicated with the
restriction of "money bills" to the House of Representatives, and the
choice of the executive. The mode in which those controversies were
finally settled being elsewhere stated, it only remains here to record
the fact that the particular nature and form of the representation in
the Senate was generally acquiesced in, when its relations to the
other branches of the government had been determined.
The difference of origin of the two branches of the legislature made
it necessary to provide for different modes of supplying the
vacancies that might occur in them. The obvious way of effecting
this in the case of a vacancy in the office of a representative was to
order a new election by the people, who can readily assemble for
such a purpose; and the duty of ordering such elections was
imposed on the executives of the States, because those
functionaries would be best informed as to the convenience of their
meeting. But the State legislatures, to whom the choice of senators
was to be confided, would be in session for only a part of the year;
and to summon them for the special purpose of filling a vacancy in
the Senate might occasion great inconvenience. The committee of
detail, therefore, provided that vacancies in the Senate might be
supplied by the executive of the State until the next meeting of its
legislature.
It is now time to turn to the examination of that great scheme of
separate and concurrent powers, which it had been proposed to
confer upon the Senate, and the suggestion of which influenced to a
great degree the qualifications of the members, their term of office,
and indeed the entire construction of this branch of the legislature.
The primary purpose of a Senate was that of a second legislative
chamber, having equal authority in all acts of legislation with the
first, the action of both being necessary to the passage of a law. As
the formation of the Constitution proceeded, from the single idea of
such a second chamber, without any special character of
representation to distinguish it from the first, up to the plan of an
equal representation of the States, there was a strong disposition
manifested to accumulate power in the body for which this peculiar
character had been gained. It had been made the depositary of a
direct and equal State influence; and this feature of the system had
become fixed and irrevocable before the powers of the other
departments, or their origin or relations, had been finally settled.
The consequence was, that for a time, wherever jealousy was felt
with regard to the executive or the judiciary,—wherever there was a
doubt about confiding in the direct action of the people,—wherever a
chasm presented itself, and the right mode of filling it did not occur,
—there was a tendency to resort to the Senate.
Thus, when the committee of detail were charged with the duty of
preparing the Constitution according to the resolutions agreed upon
in the Convention, the Senate had not only been made a legislative
body, with authority co-ordinate to that of the House, but it had
received the separate power of appointing the judges, and the
power to give a separate vote in the election of the executive. The
power to make war and treaties, the appointment of ambassadors,
and the trial of impeachments, had not been distinctly given to any
department; but the general intention to be inferred from the
resolutions was, that these matters should be vested in one or both
of the two branches of the legislature. To the executive, the duty
had been assigned, which the name of the office implies, of
executing the laws; to which had been added a revisionary check
upon legislation, and the appointment to offices in cases not
otherwise provided for. The judicial power had been described in
general and comprehensive terms, which required a particular
enumeration of the cases embraced by the principles laid down; but
it had not been distinctly foreseen, that one of the cases to which
those principles must lead would be an alleged conflict between an
act of legislation and the fundamental law of the Constitution. The
system thus marked out was carried into detail by the committee, by
vesting in the Senate the power to make treaties, to appoint
ambassadors and judges of the Supreme Court, and to adjudicate
questions of boundary between the States; by giving to the two
branches of the legislature the power to declare war; by assigning
the trial of impeachments to the Supreme Court, and enumerating
the other cases of which it was to have cognizance; and by providing
for the election of the executive by the legislature, and confining its
powers and duties to those prescribed for it by the resolutions.
It is scarcely necessary to pause for the purpose of commenting on
the practical inconveniences of some of these arrangements.
However proper it may be, in a limited and republican government,
to vest the power of declaring war in the legislative department, the
negotiation of treaties by a numerous body had been found, in our
own experience, and in that of other republics, extremely
embarrassing. However wise may be a jealousy of the executive
department, it is difficult to say that the same authority that is
intrusted with the appointment to all other offices should not be
permitted to make an ambassador or a judge. However august may
be a proceeding that is to determine a boundary between sovereign
States, it is nothing more and nothing less than a strictly judicial
controversy, capable of trial in the ordinary forms and tribunals of
judicature, besides being one that ought to be safely removed from
all political influences. However necessary it may be that an
impeachment should be conducted with the solemnities and
safeguards of allegation and proof, it is not always to be decided by
the rules with which judges are most familiar, or to be determined by
that body of law which it is their special duty to administer. However
desirable it may be, that an elective chief magistracy should be filled
with the highest capacity and fitness, and that popular tumults
should be avoided, no government has yet existed, in which the
election of such a magistrate by the legislative department has
afforded any decided advantage over an election directly or indirectly
by the people; and to give a body constituted as the American
Senate is a negative in the choice of the executive, would be
certainly inconvenient, probably dangerous.
But the position of the Senate as an assembly of the States, and
certain opinions of its superior fitness for the discharge of some of
these duties, had united to make it far too powerful for a safe and
satisfactory operation of the government. It was found to be
impossible to adjust the whole machine to the quantity of power that
had been given to one of its parts. It was eminently just and
necessary that the States should have an equal and direct
representation in some branch of the government; but that a
majority of the States, containing a minority of the people, should
possess a negative in the appointment of the executive, and in the
question of peace or war, and the sole voice in the appointment of
judges and ambassadors, was neither necessary nor proper.
Theoretically, it might seem appropriate that a question of boundary
between any two of the States represented in it should be
committed to the Senate, as a court of the peers of the sovereign
parties to the dispute; but practically, this would be a tribunal not
well fitted to try a purely judicial question. It became necessary,
therefore, to discover the true limit of that control which the nature
of the representation in the Senate was to be allowed to give to a
majority of the States. There had been some effort, in the progress
of the controversy respecting the representative system, to confine
the equal power of the States, in matters of legislation, to particular
questions or occasions; but it had turned out to be impracticable
thus to divide or limit the ordinary legislative authority of the same
body. If the Senate, as an equal assembly of the States, was to
legislate at all, it must legislate upon all subjects by the same rule
and method of suffrage. But when the question presented itself as to
the separate action of this assembly,—how far it should be invested
with the appointment of other functionaries, how far it should
control the relations of the country with foreign nations, how far it
should partake both of executive and judicial powers,—it was much
less difficult to draw the line, and to establish proper limits to the
direct agency of the States. Those limits could not indeed be
ascertained by the mere application of theoretical principles. They
were to be found in the primary necessity for reposing greater
powers in other departments, for adjusting the relations of the
system by a wider distribution of authority, and for confiding more
and more in the intelligence and virtue of the people; and therefore
it is, that, in these as in other details of the Constitution, we are to
look for the clew that is to give us the purpose and design, quite as
much to the practical compromises which constantly took place
between opposite interests, as to any triumph of any one of opposite
theories.
The first experiment that was made towards a restriction of the
power of the Senate, and an adjustment of its relations to the other
departments, was the preparation of a plan, by which the President
was to have the making of treaties, and the appointment of
ambassadors, judges of the Supreme Court, and all other officers
not otherwise provided for, by and with, the advice and consent of
the Senate. The trial of impeachments, of the President included,
was transferred to the Senate, and the trial of questions of boundary
was placed, like other controversies between States, within the
scope of the judicial power. The choice of the President was to be
made in the first instance by electors appointed by each State, in
such manner as its legislature might direct, each State to have a
number of electors equal to the whole number of its senators and
representatives in Congress; but if no one of the persons voted for
should have a majority of all the electors, or if more than one person
should have both a majority and an equal number of votes, the
Senate were to choose the President from the five highest
candidates voted for by the electors. In this plan, there was certainly
a considerable increase of the power of the President; but there was
not a sufficient diminution of the power of the Senate. The President
could nominate officers and negotiate treaties; but he must obtain
the consent of the body by whom he might have been elected, and
by whom his re-election might be determined, if he were again to
become a candidate. It appeared, therefore, to be quite necessary,
either to take away the revisionary control of the Senate over
treaties and appointments, or to devise some mode by which the
President could be made personally independent of that assembly.
He could be made independent only by taking away all agency of the
Senate in his election, or by making him ineligible to the office a
second time. There were two serious objections to the last of these
remedies,—the country might lose the services of a faithful and
experienced magistrate, whose continuance in office would be highly
important; and even in a case where no pre-eminent merit had
challenged a re-election, the effect of an election by the Senate
would always be pernicious, and must be visible throughout the
whole term of the incumbent who had been successful over four
other competitors.
And after all, what necessity was there for confiding this vast power
to the Senate, opening the door of a small body to the corruption
and intrigue for which the magnitude of the prize to be gained and
to be given, and the facility for their exercise, would furnish an
enormous temptation? Was it so necessary that the States should
force their equality of privilege and of power into every department
of the Constitution, making it felt not only in all acts of legislation,
but in the whole administration of the executive and judicial duties?
Was nothing due to the virtue and sense and patriotism of a majority
of the people of the United States? Might they not reasonably be
expected to constitute a body of electors, who, chosen for the
express purpose, and dissolved as soon as their function had been
discharged, would be able to make an upright and intelligent choice
of a chief magistrate from among the eminent citizens of the Union?
Questions like these, posterity would easily believe, without the clear
record that has descended to them, must have anxiously and deeply
employed the framers of the Constitution. They were to consider, not
only what was theoretically fit and what would practically work with
safety and success, but what would be accepted by the people for
whom they were forming these great institutions. That people
undoubtedly detested everything in the nature of a monarchy. But
there was another thing which they hated with equal intensity, and
that was an oligarchy. Their experience had given them quite as
much reason for abhorring the one as the other. Such, at least, was
their view of that experience. A king, it is true, was the chief
magistrate of the mother country against which they had rebelled,
against which they had fought successfully for their independence.
The measures that drove them into that resistance were executed by
the monarch; but those measures were planned, as they believed,
by a ministry determined to enslave them, and were sanctioned by a
Parliament in which even the so-called popular branch was then but
another phase of the aristocracy which ruled the empire. The worst
enemy our grandfathers supposed they had in England, throughout
their Revolution, was the ministerial majority of that House of
Commons, made up of placemen sitting for rotten boroughs, the
sons of peers, and the country gentlemen, who belonged to a caste
as much as their first-cousins who sat by titles in the House of Lords.
Our ancestors did not know—they went to their graves without
knowing—that in the hard, implacable temper of the king, made
harder and more implacable by a narrow and bigoted
conscientiousness, was the real cause for the persistency in that
fatal policy which severed these Colonies from his crown.
That long struggle had been over for several years, and its result
was certainly not to be regretted by the people of America. But it
had left them, as it naturally must have left them, with as strong
prejudices and jealousies against every aristocratic, as against every
monarchical institution. Public liberty in England they knew might
consist with an hereditary throne, and with a privileged and powerful
aristocracy. But public liberty in America could consist with neither.
The people of the United States could submit to restraints; they
could recognize the necessity for checks and balances in the
distribution of authority; and they understood as much of the
science of government as any people then alive. But an institution,—
however originating and however apparently necessary its peculiar
construction might be,—embracing but a small number of persons,
with power to elect the chief magistrate, with power to revise every
appointment from a chief justice down to a tidewaiter, with power to
control the President through his subordinate agents, with power to
reject every treaty that he might negotiate, and with power to sit in
judgment on his impeachment, they would not endure. "We have, in
some revolutions of this plan of government," said Randolph, "made
a bold stroke for monarchy. We are now doing the same for an
aristocracy."
How to attain the true intermediate ground, to avoid the substance
of a monarchy and the substance of an aristocracy, and yet not to
found the system on a mere democracy, was a problem not easy of
solution. All could see, that a government extended over a country
so large, which was to have the regulation of its commerce, the
collection of great revenues, the care of a vast public domain, the
superintendence of intercourse with hordes of savage tribes, the
control of relations with all the nations of the world, the
administration of a peculiar jurisprudence, and the protection of the
local constitutions from violence, must have an army and a navy,
and great fiscal, administrative, and judicial establishments,
embracing a very numerous body of public officers. To give the
appointment of such a multitude of public servants, invested with
such functions, to the unchecked authority of the President, would
be to create an executive with power not less formidable and real
than that of some monarchs, and far greater than that of others. No
one desired that a sole power of appointment should be vested in
the President alone; it was universally conceded that there must be
a revisionary control lodged somewhere, and the only question was
where it should be placed. That it ought to be in a body independent
of the executive, and not in any council of ministers that might be
assigned to him, was apparent; and there was no such body,
excepting the Senate, which united the necessary independence
with the other qualities needful for a right exercise of this power.
The negotiation of treaties was obviously a function that should be
committed to the executive alone. But a treaty might undertake to
dismember a State of part of its territory, or might otherwise affect
its individual interests; and even where it concerned only the general
interests of all the States, there was a great unwillingness to intrust
the treaty-making power exclusively to the President. Here, the
States, as equal political sovereignties, were unwilling to relax their
hold upon the general government; and the result was that provision
of the Constitution which makes the consent of two thirds of the
Senators present necessary to the ratification of a treaty.
But if it was to have these great overruling powers, the Senate must
have no voice in the appointment of the executive. There were two
modes in which the election might be arranged, so as to prevent a
mutual connection and influence between the Senate and the
President. The one was, to allow the highest number of electoral
votes to appoint the President;[164] the other was, to place the
eventual election—no person having received a majority of all the
electoral votes—in the House of Representatives. The latter plan was
finally adopted, and the Senate was thus effectually severed from a
dangerous connection with the executive.
This separation having been effected, the objections which had been
urged against the length of the senatorial term became of little
consequence. In the preparation of the plan marked out in the
resolutions sent to the committee of detail, the Senate had been
considered chiefly with reference to its legislative function; and the
purpose of those who advocated a long term of office was to
establish a body in the government of sufficient wisdom and
firmness to interpose against the impetuous counsels and levelling
tendencies of the democratic branch.[165] Six years was adopted as
an intermediate period between the longest and the shortest of the
terms proposed; and in order that there might be an infusion of
different views and tendencies from time to time, it was provided
that one third of the members should go out of office biennially.[166]
Still, in the case of each individual senator, the period of six years
was the longest of the limited terms of office created by the
Constitution. Under the Confederation, the members of the Congress
had been chosen annually, and were always liable to recall. The
people of the United States were in general strongly disposed to a
frequency of elections. A term of office for six years would be that
feature of the proposed Senate most likely, in the popular mind, to
be regarded as of an aristocratic tendency. If united with the powers
that have just passed under our review, and if to those powers it
could be said that an improper influence over the executive had
been added, the system would in all probability be rejected by the
people. But if the Senate were deprived of all agency in the
appointment of the President, it would be mere declamation to
complain of their term of office; for undoubtedly the peculiar duties
assigned to the Senate could be best discharged by those who had
had the longest experience in them. The solid objection to such a
term being removed, the complaint of aristocratic tendencies would
be confined to those who might wish to find plausible reasons for
opposition, and might not wish to be satisfied with the true reasons
for the provision.
Having now described the formation and the special powers of the
two branches of the legislature, I proceed to inquire into the origin
and history of the disqualifications to which the members were
subjected.
The Constitution of the United States was framed and established by
a generation of men, who had observed the operation upon the
English legislature of that species of influence, by the crown or its
servants, which, from the mode of its exercise, not seldom
amounting to actual bribery, has received the appropriate name of
parliamentary corruption. That generation of the American people
knew but little—they cared less—about the origin of a method of
governing the legislative body, which implies an open or a secret
venality on the part of its members, and a willingness on the part of
the administration to purchase their consent to its measures. What
they did know and what they did regard was, that for a long
succession of years the votes of members of Parliament had been
bought, with money or office, by nearly every minister who had
been at the head of affairs; that, if this practice had not been
introduced under the prince who was placed upon the throne by the
revolution of 1688, it had certainly grown to a kind of system in the
hands of the statesmen by whom that revolution was effected, and
had attained its greatest height under the first two princes of the
house of Hanover; that it was freely and sometimes shamefully
applied throughout the American war; and that, down to that day,
no British statesman had had the sagacity to discover, and the virtue
to adopt, a purer system of administration.[167] Whether this was a
necessary vice of the English constitution; whether it was inherent or
temporary; or whether it was only a stage in the development of
parliamentary government, destined to pass away when the
relations of the representative body to the people had become better
settled,—could not then be seen even in England. But to our
ancestors, when framing their Constitution, it presented itself as a
momentous fact; whose warning was not the less powerful, because
it came from the centre of institutions with which they had been
most familiar, and from the country to which they traced their origin,
—a country in which parliamentary government had had the fairest
chances for success that the world had witnessed.
Yet it would not have been easy at that time, as it is not at the
present, and as it may never be, to define with absolute precision
the true limits which executive influence with the legislative body
should not be suffered to pass. Still less is it easy to say that such
influence ought not to exist at all;[168] although it is not difficult to
say that there are methods in which it should not be suffered to be
exercised. The more elevated and more clear-sighted public morality
of the present age, in England and in America, condemns with equal
severity and equal justice both the giver and the receiver in every
transaction that can be regarded as a purchase of votes upon
particular measures or occasions, whatever may have been the
consideration or motive of the bargain. But whether that morality
goes, or ought to go, farther,—whether it includes, or ought to
include, in the same condemnation, every form of influence by which
an administration can add extrinsic weight to the merits of its
measures,—is a question that admits of discussion.
It may be said, assuming the good intentions of an administration,
and the correctness of its policy and measures, that its policy and its
measures should address themselves solely to the patriotism and
sense of right of the members of the legislative department. But an
ever active patriotism and a never failing sense of right are not
always, if often, to be found; the members of a legislative body are
men, with the imperfections, the failings, and the passions of men;
and if pure patriotism and right perceptions of duty are alone relied
upon, they may, and sometimes inevitably will be, found wanting.
On the other hand, it is just as true, that the persons composing
every administration are mere men, and that it will not do to assume
their wisdom and good intentions as the sole foundations on which
to rest the public security, leaving them at liberty to use all the
appliances that may be found effectual for gaining right ends, and
overlooking the character of the means. One of the principal reasons
for the establishment of different departments, in the class of
governments to which ours belongs, is, that perfect virtue and
unerring wisdom are not to be predicated of any man in any station.
If they were, a simple despotism would be the best and the only
necessary form of government.
All correct reasoning on this subject, and all true construction of
governments like ours, must commence with two propositions, one
of which embraces a truth of political science, and the other a truth
of general morals. The first is, that, while the different functions of
government are to be distributed among different persons, and to be
kept distinctly separated, in order that there may be both division of
labor and checks against the abuse of power, it is occasionally
necessary that some room should be allowed for supplying the want
of wisdom or virtue in one department by the wisdom or virtue of
another. In matters of government depending on mere discretion,
unlimited confidence cannot with safety be placed anywhere.[169]
The other proposition is the very plain axiom in morals, that, while in
all human transactions there may be bad means employed to effect
a worthy object, the character of those means can never be altered,
nor their use justified, by the character of the end. With these two
propositions admitted, what is to be done is to discover that
arrangement of the powers and relations of the different
departments whose acts involve, more or less, the exercise of pure
discretion, which will give the best effect to both of these truths; and
as all government and all details of government, to be useful, must
be practically adapted to the nature of man, it will be found that an
approximation in practice to a perfect theory is all that can be
attained.
Thus the general duties and powers of the legislative and the
executive departments are capable of distinct separation. The one is
to make, the other is to execute the laws. But execution of the laws
of necessity involves administration, and administration makes it
necessary that there should be an executive policy. To carry out that
policy requires new laws; authority must be obtained to do acts not
before authorized; and supplies must be perpetually renewed. The
executive stands therefore in a close relation to the legislative
department;—a relation which makes it necessary for the one to
appeal frequently, and indeed constantly, to the discretion of the
other. If the executive is left at liberty to purchase what it believes or
alleges to be the right exercise of that discretion, by the
inducements of money or office applied to a particular case, the rule
of common morals is violated; conscience becomes false to duty, and
corruption, having once entered the body politic, may be employed
to effect bad ends as well as good. Nay, as bad ends will stand most
in need of its influence, it will be applied the most grossly where the
object to be attained is the most culpable. On the other hand, if the
members of the legislative body, by being made incapable of
accepting the higher or more lucrative offices of state, are cut off
from those inducements to right conduct and a true ambition which
the imperfections of our nature have made not only powerful, but
sometimes necessary, aids to virtue, the public service may have no
other security than their uncertain impulses or imperfect judgments.
In the midst of such tendencies to opposite mischiefs, all that human
wisdom and foresight can do is, to anticipate and prevent the evils
of both extremes, by provisions which will guard both the interests
of morality and the interests of political expediency as completely as
circumstances will allow.
I am persuaded it was upon such principles as I have thus
endeavored to state, that the framers of our national Constitution
intended to regulate this very difficult part of the relations between
the executive and the legislature. During a considerable period,
however, of their deliberations on the disabilities to which it would
be proper to subject the members of the latter department, they had
another example before them besides that afforded by the history of
parliamentary corruption in England. The Congress of the
Confederation had of course the sole power of appointment to
offices under the authority of the United States; and although there
is no reason to suppose that body at any time to have been justly
chargeable with corrupt motives, there were complaints of the
frequency with which it had filled the offices which it had created
with its own members. In these complaints, the people overlooked
the justification. They forgot that the nature of the government, and
the circumstances of the country, rendered it difficult for an
assembly which both made and filled the offices, and which
exercised its functions at a time when the State governments
absorbed by far the greater part of the interests and attention of
their citizens, to find suitable men out of its own ranks. In that
condition of things, it might have been expected,—and it implies no
improper purpose,—that offices would be sometimes framed or
regulated with a view to their being filled by particular persons. But
the complaints existed;[170] the evil was one that tended constantly
to become worse; and, in framing the new government, this was the
first aspect in which the influence of office and its emoluments
presented itself to the Convention.
For when the Virginia members, through Edmund Randolph, brought
forward their scheme of government, they not only gave the
executive no power of appointment to any office, but they proposed
to vest the appointment of both the executive and the judiciary in
the legislature. Hence they felt the necessity of guarding against the
abuse that might follow, if the members of the legislature were to be
left at liberty to appoint each other to office,—an abuse which they
knew had been imputed to the Congress, and which they declared
had been grossly practised by their own legislature.[171] They
proposed, therefore, to go beyond the Confederation, and to make
the members of both branches ineligible to any office established
under the authority of the United States, (excepting those peculiarly
belonging to their own functions,) during their term of service and
for one year after its expiration. This provision passed the committee
of the whole; but in the Convention, on a motion made by Mr.
Gorham to strike it out, the votes of the States were divided. An
effort was then made by Mr. Madison to find a middle ground,
between an eligibility in all cases and an absolute disqualification. If
the unnecessary creation of offices and the increase of salaries was
the principal evil to be anticipated, he believed that the door might
be shut against that abuse, and might properly be left open for the
appointment of members to places not affected by their own votes,
as an encouragement to the legislative service. But there were
several of the stern patriots of the Convention who insisted on a
total exclusion, and who denied that there was any such necessity
for holding out inducements to enter the legislature.[172] This was a
question on which different minds, of equal sagacity and equal
purity, would naturally arrive at different conclusions. Still, it is
apparent that the mischiefs most apprehended at the time of Mr.
Madison's proposition would be in a great degree prevented, by
taking from the legislature the power of appointing to office; and
that this modification of the system was what was needed, to make
his plan a true remedy for the abuses that had been displayed in our
own experience. The stigma of venality cannot properly be applied
to the laudable ambition of rising into the honorable offices of a free
government; and if the opportunity to create places, or to increase
their emoluments, and then to secure those places, is taken away,
by vesting the appointment in the executive, the question turns
mainly on the relations that ought to exist between that department
and the legislature. But Mr. Madison's suggestion was made before it
was ascertained that the executive would have any power of
appointment, and it was accordingly rejected;—a majority of the
delegations considering it best to retain the ineligibility in all cases,
as proposed by the Virginia plan.[173] In this way, the disqualification
became incorporated into the first draft of the Constitution, prepared
by the committee of detail.[174]
But by this time it was known that a large part of the patronage of
the government must be placed in the hands of the President; for it
had been settled that he was to appoint to all offices not otherwise
provided for, and the cases thus excepted were those of judges and
ambassadors, which stood, in this draft of the Constitution, vested in
the Senate. A strong opposition to this arrangement, however, had
already manifested itself, and the result was very likely to be,—as it
in fact turned out,—that nearly the whole of the appointments would
be made on the nomination of the President, even if the Senate
were to be empowered to confirm or reject them. Accordingly, when
this clause came under consideration, the principle of an absolute
disqualification for office was vigorously attacked, and as vigorously
defended. The inconvenience and impolicy of excluding officers of
the army and navy from the legislature; of rendering it impossible
for the executive to select a commander-in-chief from among the
members, in cases of pre-eminent fitness; of refusing seats to the
heads of executive departments; and of closing the legislature as an
avenue to other branches of the public service,—were all strenuously
urged and denied.[175] At length, a middle course became
necessary, to reconcile all opinions. By a very close vote, the
ineligibility was restrained to cases in which the office had been
created, or the emolument of it increased, during the term of
membership;[176] and a seat in the legislature was made
incompatible with any other office under the United States.[177]
Some at least of the probable sources of corruption were cut off by
these provisions. The executive can make no bargain for a vote, by
the promise of an office which has been acted upon by the member
whose vote is sought for; and there can be no body of placemen,
ready at all times to sell their votes as the price for which they are
permitted to retain their places. At the same time, the executive is
not deprived of the influence which attends the power of appointing
to offices not created, or the emoluments of which have not been
increased, by any Congress of which the person appointed has been
a member. This influence is capable of abuse; it is also capable of
being honorably and beneficially exerted. Whether it shall be
employed corruptly or honestly, for good or for bad purposes, is left
by the Constitution to the restraints of personal virtue and the
chastisements of public opinion.
A serious question, however, has been made, whether the interests
of the public service, involved in the relations of the two
departments, would not have been placed upon a better footing, if
some of the higher officers of state had been admitted to hold seats
in the legislature. Under the English constitution, there is no practical
difficulty, at least in modern times, in determining the general
principle that is to distinguish between the class of officers who can,
and those who cannot, be usefully allowed to have seats in the
House of Commons. The principle which, after much inconsistent
legislation and many abortive attempts to legislate, has generally
been acted on since the reign of George II., is, that it is both
necessary and useful to have in that House some of the higher
functionaries of the administration; but that it is not at all necessary,
and not useful, to allow the privilege of sitting in Parliament to
subordinate officers.[178] The necessity of the case arises altogether
from the peculiar relations of the ministry to the crown, and of the
latter to the Commons. If the executive government were not
admitted, through any of its members, to explain and vindicate its
measures, to advocate new grants of authority, or to defend the
prerogatives of the crown, the popular branch of the legislature
would either become the predominant power in the state, or sink
into insignificance. This is conceded by the severest writers on the
English government.
But when we pass from a civil polity which it has taken centuries to
produce, and which has had its departments adjusted much less by
reference to exact principles than by the results of their successive
struggles for supremacy over each other, and when we come to an
original distribution of powers, in the arrangements of a constitution
made entire and at once by a single act of the national will, we must
not give too much effect to analogies which after all are far from
being complete. In preparing the Constitution of the United States,
its framers had no prerogative, in any way resembling that of the
crown of England, to consider and provide for. The separate powers
to be conferred on the chief magistracy—aside from its concurrence
in legislation—were simply executive and administrative; the office
was to be elective, and not hereditary; and its functions, like those
of the legislature, were to be prescribed with all the exactness of
which a written instrument is capable. There was, therefore, little of
such danger that the one department would silently or openly
encroach on the rights or usurp the powers of the other, as there is
where there exists hereditary right on the one side and customary
right on the other, and where the boundaries between the two
departments are to be traced by the aid of ancient traditions, or
collected from numerous and perhaps conflicting precedents. There
was no such necessity, therefore, as there is in England, for placing
members of the administration in the legislature, in order to
preserve the balance of the Constitution. The sole question with us
was, whether the public convenience required that the
administration should be able to act directly upon the course of
legislation. The prevailing opinion was that this was not required.
This opinion was undoubtedly formed under the fear of corruption
and the jealousy of executive power, chiefly produced—and justly
produced—by the example of what had long existed in England.
That the error, if any was committed, lay on the safer side, none can
doubt. It is possible that the chances of a corrupt influence would
not have been increased, and that the opportunities for a salutary
influence might have been enlarged,—as it is highly probable that
the convenience of communication would have been promoted,—if
some of the higher officers of state could have been allowed to hold
seats in either house of Congress. But it is difficult to see how this
could have been successfully practised, under the system of
representation and election which the framers of the Constitution
were obliged to establish: and perhaps this is a decisive answer to
the objection.[179]
Among the powers conceded by the Constitution to the legislature of
each State is that of prescribing the time, place, and manner of
holding the elections of its senators and representatives in Congress.
This provision[180] originated with the committee of detail; but, as it
was reported by them, there was no other authority reserved to
Congress itself than that of altering the regulations of the States;
and this authority extended as well to the place of choosing the
senators, as to all the other circumstances of the election.[181] In
the Convention, however, the authority of Congress was extended
beyond the alteration of State regulations, so as to embrace a power
to make rules, as well as to alter those made by the States. But the
place of choosing the senators was excepted altogether from this
restraining authority, and left to the States.[182] Mr. Madison, in his
minutes, adds the explanation, that the power of Congress to make
regulations was supplied, in order to enable them to regulate the
elections, if the States should fail or refuse to do so.[183] But the
text of the Constitution, as finally settled, gives authority to
Congress at "any time" to "make or alter such regulations"; and this
would seem to confer a power, which, when exercised, must be
paramount, whether a State regulation exists at the time or not.
There is one other peculiarity of the American legislature, of which it
is proper in this connection to give a brief account; namely, the
compensation of its members for their public services. In the plan
presented by the Virginia delegation, it was proposed that the
members of both branches should receive "liberal stipends"; but it
was not suggested whether they were to be paid by the States, or
from the national treasury. The committee of the whole determined
to adopt the latter mode of payment; and as the representation in
both branches, according to the first decision, was to be of the same
character, no reason was then suggested for making a difference in
the source of their compensation. But when the construction of the
Senate was considered in the Convention, the idea was suggested
that this body ought in some way to represent wealth; and it was
apparently under the influence of this suggestion, that, after a
refusal to provide for a payment of the senators by their States,
payment out of the national treasury was stricken from the
resolution under debate.[184] There was thus introduced into the
resolutions sent to the committee of detail, a discrepancy between
the modes of compensating the members of the two branches; for
while the members of the House were to be paid "an adequate
compensation" out of "the public treasury," the Senate were to
receive "a compensation for the devotion of their time to the public
service," but the source of payment was not designated. But when
the whole body of those resolutions had been acted on, the
character of the representation in the Senate had been settled, and
the idea of its being made a representation of wealth, in any sense,
had been rejected. The committee of detail had, therefore, in giving
effect to the decisions of the Convention, to consider merely whether
the members of the two branches should be paid by their States, or
from the national treasury; and for the purpose of making the same
provision as to both, and in order to avoid the question whether the
Constitution should establish the amount, or should leave it to be
regulated by the Congress itself, they provided that the members of
each house should receive a compensation for their services, to be
ascertained and paid by the State in which they should be chosen.
[185]
In the examination which has thus far been made of the process of
forming the Constitution, the reader will have noticed the absence of
any express provisions concerning the regulation of commerce, and
the obtaining of revenues. A system of government had been
framed, embracing a national legislature, in which the mode of
representation alone had been determined with precision. The
powers of this legislature had been described only in very general
terms. It was to have "the legislative rights vested in Congress by
the Confederation," and the power "to legislate in all cases for the
general interests of the Union, and also in those to which the States
were separately incompetent, or in which the harmony of the United
States may be interrupted by the exercise of individual legislation."
It might undoubtedly have been considered that, as the want of a
power in the Confederation to make uniform commercial regulations
affecting the foreign and domestic relations of the States was one of
the principal causes of the assembling of this Convention, such a
power was implied in the terms of the resolution, which had
declared the general principles on which the authority of the national
legislature ought to be regulated. Still, it remained to be determined
what kind of regulation of commerce was required by "the general
interests of the Union," or how far the States were incompetent, by
their separate legislation, to deal with the interests of commerce so
as to promote "the harmony of the United States." In the same way,
a power to obtain revenues might be implied on the same general
principles. But whether the commercial power foreshadowed in
these broad declarations was to be limited or unlimited; whether
Welcome to our website – the ideal destination for book lovers and
knowledge seekers. With a mission to inspire endlessly, we offer a
vast collection of books, ranging from classic literary works to
specialized publications, self-development books, and children's
literature. Each book is a new journey of discovery, expanding
knowledge and enriching the soul of the reade
Our website is not just a platform for buying books, but a bridge
connecting readers to the timeless values of culture and wisdom. With
an elegant, user-friendly interface and an intelligent search system,
we are committed to providing a quick and convenient shopping
experience. Additionally, our special promotions and home delivery
services ensure that you save time and fully enjoy the joy of reading.
ebookname.com