Using Figurative Language Herbert L Colston instant download
Using Figurative Language Herbert L Colston instant download
download
https://ebookbell.com/product/using-figurative-language-herbert-
l-colston-5303502
Using Ibm Spss Statistics For Research Methods And Social Science
Statistics 7th Edition 7th William E Wagner
https://ebookbell.com/product/using-ibm-spss-statistics-for-research-
methods-and-social-science-statistics-7th-edition-7th-william-e-
wagner-44871284
https://ebookbell.com/product/using-digital-humanities-in-the-
classroom-a-practical-introduction-for-teachers-lecturers-and-
students-2nd-edition-2nd-claire-battershill-46136488
https://ebookbell.com/product/using-social-emotional-learning-to-
prevent-school-violence-a-reference-and-activity-guide-allison-
paolini-46192334
https://ebookbell.com/product/using-video-games-to-level-up-
collaboration-for-students-a-fun-practical-way-to-support-
socialemotional-skills-development-matthew-harrison-46192336
Using Open Educational Resources To Promote Social Justice 1st Edition
Cj Ivory Editor
https://ebookbell.com/product/using-open-educational-resources-to-
promote-social-justice-1st-edition-cj-ivory-editor-46495310
https://ebookbell.com/product/using-scenarios-scenario-planning-for-
improving-organizations-thomas-j-chermack-46715688
Using The Iso 56002 Innovation Management System A Practical Guide For
Implementation And Building A Culture Of Innovation H James Harrington
Sid Benraouane
https://ebookbell.com/product/using-the-iso-56002-innovation-
management-system-a-practical-guide-for-implementation-and-building-a-
culture-of-innovation-h-james-harrington-sid-benraouane-46774092
https://ebookbell.com/product/using-dignities-in-astrology-charles-
obert-46787326
https://ebookbell.com/product/using-art-for-social-transformation-
international-perspective-for-social-workers-community-workers-and-
art-therapists-1st-edition-eltje-bos-47190580
Using Figurative Language
Using Figurative Language presents results from a multidisciplinary
decades-long study of figurative language that addresses the question, “Why
don’t people just say what they mean?” This research empirically investigates
goals speakers or writers have when speaking (writing) figuratively and, con-
comitantly, meaning effects wrought by figurative language usage. These prag-
matic effects arise from many kinds of figurative language, including metaphors
(e.g., “This computer is a dinosaur”), verbal irony (e.g., “Nice place you’ve got
here”), idioms (e.g., “Bite the bullet”), proverbs (e.g., “Don’t put all your eggs
in one basket”), and others. Reviewed studies explore mechanisms – linguistic,
psychological, social, and others – underlying pragmatic effects, some traced to
basic processes embedded in human sensory, perceptual, embodied, cognitive,
social, and schematic functioning. The book should interest readers, research-
ers, and scholars in fields beyond psychology, linguistics, and philosophy who
share interests in figurative language – including language studies, communi-
cation, literary criticism, neuroscience, semiotics, rhetoric, and anthropology.
Herbert L. Colston
University of Alberta
32 Avenue of the Americas, New York, NY 10013-2473, USA
www.cambridge.org
Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9781107105652
© Herbert L. Colston 2015
This publication is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception
and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements,
no reproduction of any part may take place without the written
permission of Cambridge University Press.
First published 2015
A catalog record for this publication is available from the British Library.
Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data
Colston, Herbert L.
Using figurative language / Herbert Colston.
pages cm
Includes bibliographical references and index.
ISBN 978-1-107-10565-2 (hardback)
1. Figures of speech. 2. Psycholinguistics. 3. Sociolinguistics. I. Title.
P37.5.F53C65 2015
808′.032–dc23 2015023013
ISBN 978-1-107-10565-2 Hardback
Cambridge University Press has no responsibility for the persistence or accuracy of URLs
for external or third-party Internet websites referred to in this publication and does not
guarantee that any content on such websites is, or will remain, accurate or appropriate.
To Herbert A. Colston
and
Marlene D. Colston
You don’t know anything,
unless you know everything.
You never know everything,
so you always know nothing.
Contents
1 Why Don’t People Say What They Mean? Wealth and Stealth 1
Brief Overview 4
Introduction of Themes 4
Pragmatic Meaning and Pragmatic Effects 5
Psychology and Pragmatics 6
Figurative Language as a Complex Social Phenomenon 7
Complexity Approaches 7
Caveats 7
Pop Goes the Examples 8
Problems with Problems 9
Figurative Name Calling 9
A Final Theme: Rorschach Figures 10
vii
viii Contents
Impoliteness 78
Tension Reduction 81
Machiavellianism 81
Anomalous Pragmatic Effects 82
Causes of Pragmatic Effects 85
Linguistic Causes 87
Structural Causes 88
Juxtaposition Causes 89
Metapragmatic Causes 90
Social Causes 90
Psychological Causes 91
Associative Causes 96
Idiosyncratic Causes 97
Stylistic/Register Causes 97
Embodied Causes 97
Time Course of Pragmatic Effects 98
Midpoint Conclusions 98
Aptness 128
Indirectness 131
The Future of Common Ground 131
Packaging Figurative Language 133
Pragmatic Effects for Speakers 141
Notes 231
References 239
Index 263
Acknowledgments
xiii
Preface
Using Figurative Language was born out of the idea that accounts of lan-
guage production, use, comprehension, structure, underpinning, and
change, for figurative and indirect but additionally all language, need to
align with current understandings of not only human cognitive phenom-
ena but also social, emotional, motivational, physical, and other human
and animal functioning along with established explications of the all the
layers of language and their nature. In kind with the cognitive commit-
ment, the scientific study of language conducted by allied disciplines needs
also to adhere to a social commitment, a developmental commitment, an
embodied commitment, and commitments to emotional, evolutionary,
and other domains of human structure and operation, as well as to their
complex interaction, to fully portray the processes and products stemming
from human linguistic communication. Some of these source data come
from research in the array of subdisciplines in psychology. Other input can
be found in evolutionary theory, biology, the functioning of communica-
tion systems parallel to language, linguistics proper, cognitive linguistics,
literary studies, semiotics, rhetoric, and other disciplines that focus on the
processes and products or both of linguistic communion.
Particular focus was put on the social underpinnings of abstract thought
and, in turn, language cognition given recent developments in sociocogni-
tive neuroscience and embodiment research, which provides evidence that
a major portion of how we do cognition and, accordingly, how we do lan-
guage is wired to align with our level of connection with other people or
groups and our status in social hierarchies – along with concomitant social
motivations produced by such hierarchies. How our cognitive functions are
tuned is related closely to how we operate as part of a human social group.
These social constraints and corrallings, along with parallel embodied ones,
xv
newgenprepdf
xvi Preface
1
2 Why Don’t People Say What They Mean?
Verbal Irony
andrew: “That’s real intelligent.”
bender: “You richies are so smart.”
bender: “Well . . . I’ll just run right out and join the wrestling team.”
Hyperbole
allison: “You do everything everybody ever tells you to do; that is
a problem!”
andrew: “You’ve never competed in your whole life!”
bender: “Screws fall out all the time; the world’s an imperfect place.”
Understatement
allison: “My home life is . . . unsatisfying.”
andrew: “Yeah . . . he’s kinda . . . he’s kinda skinny, weak.”
vernon: “Alright people, we’re gonna try something a little different
today.”
Colloquial Tautology
vernon: “Here we are.”
brian: “That’s what it is.”
vernon: “Alright, that’s it.”
Mixed Figures
(Note that although some mixing is found in the individual figure
groupings, the “mixed” figures here are relatively stronger, containing
mixtures of at least three types.)
allison: “It’s kind of a double-edged sword, isn’t it?” (rhetorical ques-
tion, understatement, idiom, metaphor).
bender: “Oh and wouldn’t that be a bite, missing a whole wrestling
meet” (irony, metaphor, rhetorical question).
vernon: “I’ve got you for the rest of your natural born life if you don’t
watch your step!” (hyperbole, metaphor, idiom, metonymy).
bender: “Although you’d probably have to ride in the back seat, ‘cause
his nuts would ride shotgun” (metaphor, hyperbole, idiom).
bender: “Well, Brian’s trying to tell me that in addition to the number
of girls in the Niagara Falls area, that presently you and he are
riding the hobby horse!” (irony, metaphor, euphemism).
vernon: “Ah, ah, ah grab some wood there, bub!” (metonymy, unin-
tended double entendre – resulting in situational irony).
bender: “Hey, how come Andrew gets to get up? If he gets up, we’ll all
get up; it’ll be anarchy!” (rhetorical question, hyperbole, irony).
claire: “You don’t say anything all day, and then when you open your
mouth . . . you unload all these tremendous lies all over me”
(hyperbole, metonymy, metaphor).
Why Don’t People Say What They Mean? 3
and hands to share hearts and minds (metonymy) and usually without our
noticing – as hearers and even speakers. Indeed, one tiny bit (understatement)
of the motivation driving the question “Why don’t people just say what they
mean?” is this lack of apparentness of figurative language in normal every-
day talk and text. People just don’t see it for what it is (colloquial tautology).
They don’t see how drenched (metaphor) normal language is with figures
and indirectness and all that those forms accomplish. People instead focus
on rarer instances where a perhaps novel figurative usage goes awry and
then accordingly question why it is there. By way of illustrating figurative
transparency, each of the figures explicitly labeled in this and the preceding
paragraph are also present in the much shorter paragraph preceding them.
Brief Overview
The book attempts to provide the long answer to the rhetorical question
in this chapter’s title. It considers the wide array of figurative kinds of lan-
guage to delineate different ways in which figurative and other language
accomplishes complex additional meanings for speakers and writers. In
so doing, it first addresses the basic question of what this additional com-
plex meaning is (Chapter 2). It then discusses the myriad of types of these
meanings, including which kinds of figurative language accomplish them
and how (Chapter 3). Chapter 4 then treats factors surrounding how peo-
ple use figurative language to leverage these meanings. Particular focus
is given to how much people attend to what they and their interlocutors
know when using figurative language and how this interacts with different
kinds of figures. Other delivery factors concerning how to present figura-
tive language to maximize its additional meaning output are also consid-
ered. A discussion of the prevalence of figurative language usage and its
leveraged additional meanings, along with limitations and potential expan-
sion of those additional meanings, is provided in Chapter 5. Chapter 6 then
brings together the themes of the preceding chapters and offers several
take-home messages for future research on figurative and indirect (and,
indeed, all language) usage. To prepare the stage for this discussion, sev-
eral of these themes need to be briefly introduced and a couple of caveats
presented to corral the issues detailed in forthcoming chapters.
Introduction of Themes
Five primary ideas will emerge across subsequent chapters. One appears
right away in Chapter 2 concerning the nature of the “additional complex
Introduction of Themes 5
meaning” termed thus far in the use of figurative language – the notion of
a pragmatic effect. The latter four ideas can help to orient progress through
Chapters 2 through 5 but will become most prominent in Chapter 6. These
involve (1) the role that varieties of psychological phenomena play in lan-
guage processing – predominantly for figurative language but not isolated
to it; (2) figurative language use and comprehension as a social phenom-
enon; and (3) approaches for dealing with the complexity of figurative cog-
nition and the impact of broad discourse content on identification of local
isolated figures. This latter theme is introduced at the end of this chapter
(see the section entitled, “A Final Theme: Rorschach Figures”).
Complexity Approaches
This complex tangle of human interaction systems calls for adoption of
models of representation and, to an extent, prediction that embrace mul-
tiple interacting inputs as well as constraints and affordances on output that
often supersede current relatively simple causal models of communication
functioning. Approaches to figurative language based on constraint satis-
faction (Campbell & Katz 2012; Pexman 2008), dynamical systems (Gibbs &
Colston 2012; Gibbs & van Orden 2012), or other elaborate multivari-
ate accounting hold promise at juggling this complexity because they are
designed to provide probabilistic outcome estimates based on a range of
interacting input parameters.
Caveats
Two brief caveats on the overall treatment given to figurative language and
its pragmatic effects are warranted here given the different disciplines in
which researchers on figurative language reside. Values placed on types
of data in linguistic, psycholinguistic, and psychological research, among
other fields, differ according to one’s home discipline and subarea. Concerns
8 Why Don’t People Say What They Mean?
practice, along with regular usage of the term figurative, problems remain
with attempted delineation between these as categories. Many presumed
figurative utterances are difficult to categorize into subsets of known figura-
tive types. Many supposed nonfigurative utterances also may be borderline
figurative.
One need only look at the examples at the beginning of this chapter to
see this. The first rhetorical question by Claire contains an extreme-case
formulation that gives it a flavor of hyperbole. The second idiom by Andrew
has hints of both understatement and hyperbole. The second irony example
from Bender could be metonymic and hyperbolic, and its use of diminu-
tivization could be a second source of subtle irony. All three of these deli-
cate suggestions or invocations of figurative mechanisms, plus many others,
also can be found easily in what most people would take as nonfigurative
language.
really think I give a shit?” Finally, Bender ceases pushing back and is obvi-
ously furious, and a bit dejected, at Vernon especially but perhaps also at
himself for having gotten stuck with two more months of weekend deten-
tion. Bender then salvos two final figurative comments in rapid sequence,
responding to Vernon’s gloating that he had Bender for two months (“I got-
cha”). The first is delivered in a very snide tone; the second with fury. Vernon
then responds also angrily (Vernon’s response is the target utterance).
this observation. Thus his statement (1.3) may simply reflect this – he is
confident that Bender is trying to get the others to think that he is at ease
with or happy about the added detention. Vernon does use a few standard
verbal irony markers (e.g., extreme case formulations, emphases added,
“I’m sure . . .,” “that’s exactly . . .”), but they do not seem to readily map onto
irony. One thus could argue that they do not raise the comment to irony
status. “I’m sure . . .” may just express Vernon’s confidence in his observa-
tion, and “that’s exactly . . .” may just note the precision of what Bender is
seeking to convey.
But Vernon’s interpretation of Bender’s comments (1.1 and 1.2) as
attempted lies, along with knowledge about both Vernon’s and Bender’s
personalities, their feelings toward one another, and the deeper history,
indicated and schematic/stereotypical information triggered by the longer
previous discourse, indeed going back to the beginning of the film, may
in fact demonstrate Vernon’s response as subtly ironic. Moreover, Vernon’s
ironizing Bender’s motivation in using comments (1.1) and (1.2) may be a
case of a subtle verbal irony embedded within dramatic irony.
For the verbal irony, Vernon’s expression in comment (1.3) could be
making fun of what he sees as Bender’s weak facade. According to Vernon,
Bender is deeply upset and hurt at his punishment but is trying to convince
the others that he is not. So Bender puts up statements saying that he is
nonplussed and indeed happy about the situation, even if his delivery obvi-
ously reveals his true feelings. Vernon sees this as a lame attempt. Vernon’s
personality, as revealed in the discourses leading up to this scene, bears
on this – Vernon is not a man of great depth, empathy, or insight. Or at
least he doesn’t practice these qualities. He bitterly sees only the surface
form of people, their expressions, and behavior and usually takes a nega-
tive interpretation of them when other understandings are available. All of
this is because Vernon views young people with contempt. Young people
in Vernon’s view are nothing but a rebellious mob challenging his social
power, strength, and desire to maintain discipline.
Thus Vernon’s rebuttal to Bender may instead be his seeing only the sim-
plest, and worst, motivation Bender might have – lying and, in not liking
Bender’s supposed dishonesty, seeking to ironize it. Vernon achieves this
through an ever so slightly feigned agreement that convincing the others
with comments (1.1) and (1.2) is viable and that Bender’s motivation to do so is
commendable. The extreme-case formulations now fit nicely – “I’m sure . . .”
hints that the likelihood that others will be convinced by Bender’s com-
ments is high, and “. . . that’s exactly” commends the quality of what Bender
is seeking to convey. In this pretense, though, Vernon reveals his true belief
A Final Theme: Rorschach Figures 13
that Bender’s statements have no chance of convincing the others and that
his motivation is instead pathetic.
In an isolated sense, Vernon is right about this. Bender is indeed tele-
graphing the message that he is resigned and happy, and no one is likely to
believe this. But Vernon greatly misses the bigger picture. Bender’s use of
verbal irony isn’t an attempt to masquerade as a person happy with his lot.
It’s instead a complex way of saying that he’s not happy by ironically negat-
ing the idea that he is happy. This is apparent by Bender’s obvious emotional
displays and clear intelligence in using language.
All told, therefore, Vernon’s response is to belittle only the portion of
Bender’s broader expression system that Vernon can see – the resignation/
happiness statements – which Vernon thinks Bender is genuinely trying to
pass as counterfeit. This makes Vernon’s response (1.3) also a case of tragic
irony – Vernon thinks one thing is going on when something contradictory
(and larger) is going on instead, to which Vernon is oblivious. Vernon is
claiming that Bender is being dishonest when, in fact, Bender is expressing
the truth.
Two important points from this example are worth emphasizing. The
first is how the emotion and multimodal cues shown by Bender are carry-
ing half the weight of his irony – he’s clearly furious and despondent but
says (ironically) that he is resigned and happy (1.1 and 1.2). So all the non-
linguistic indications of emotion and stance are very much a part of what
Bender is ultimately saying and interact deeply with the linguistic process-
ing taking place – emotions and nonverbal cues are things we process very
deeply and quickly.
The second point is the broader discourse and contextual impact on
narrower individual turns. To understand even that Vernon is being ironic
in comment (1.3), as well as the invalidity revealed in the narrowness of
that expression and the broader dramatic irony it creates, one must really
look at content in the broader previous discourse and the overall context.
Otherwise, Vernon’s supposed nonfigurative assertion that Bender is sim-
ply faking happiness to the other people when he really feels otherwise
might seem accurate, might seem to reveal Bender’s dishonesty, might
seem aligned with Vernon’s supposed objectively nonfigurative statement,
and might seem the end of the story. When viewed in the broader sense of
Bender’s life, obvious intelligence, sense of inequity, means of expression,
and ultimate honesty, however, along with Vernon’s bitterness, prejudices,
and narrowness of view and the longer and shorter history between these
two people, then the verbal and tragic ironies become apparent.
2
14
What Is a Pragmatic Effect? 15
questions, and similes. The participants were asked first to read the exam-
ples, then to generate other examples of those figures on their own, and
finally to list reasons why individuals might use the particular forms in a
discourse. The responses to the latter motivation question then were orga-
nized into a taxonomy of discourse goals, and a calculation of the degree of
overlap among these reasons was made.
This work has been cited extensively by researchers conducting subse-
quent specific empirical research addressing why people would use differ-
ent kinds of figurative language. It empirically demarked the wide range of
goals that actual native speakers (of American English) report are accom-
plished by varieties of figurative language. It also measured the varying
extent to which each figure accomplishes each goal. It additionally demon-
strated the ranging degree of overlap in what different figures were reported
to accomplish.
The findings overall revealed a great deal of subtlety and diversity in what
different figures accomplish. Seemingly unrelated figures, for instance, were
often shown to accomplish similar goals. Irony and simile as one example
had a relatively high overlap score of 0.52 (the absolute range of this score
is between 0 for no overlap in accomplished goals and 1 for perfect overlap;
see Graesser [1981] for an explanation of how these scores are calculated).
The figures also were shown to each accomplish a large number of differ-
ent goals. Indeed, of the total number of nineteen unique discourse goals
reported for all the figures (not including miscellaneous goals collectively
labeled “other”), the average number of goals accomplished by the figures
was 14.6 (77 percent of all the possible goals). This diversity also was shared
by the figures rather than being concentrated on only a few highly multi-
purpose ones (the range was twelve to eighteen goals per figure, or 63 to
95 percent of all goals mentioned).
Although this subtlety and diversity of functioning of figures are quite
interesting in their own right, they can nonetheless shroud deeper patterns
in what figures primarily or most strongly accomplish. Thus, for present
purposes, a brief reanalysis of the findings of Roberts and Kreuz (1994)
is provided with a truncation that focuses only on the goals for which a
high degree of agreement existed among the study participants concerning
which figures achieve which goals. The discussion is then limited to figures
for which more than 50 percent of the study participants reported a given
goal was accomplished.
An interesting pattern emerges when figures and discourse goals are
viewed with this truncation. The discourse goals that at least half the
18 What Is a Pragmatic Effect?
Goal Figure
Organized differently, the figures that at least half the participants said
accomplished a discourse goal(s) are as follows (for present purposes, met-
aphor and simile are combined):
Figure Goal
of action in other people), the Roberts and Kreuz study did not, however,
explicitly discuss how the discourse goals they collected fit into broader
interpersonal, social, or pragmatic theories. Nor did it elaborate on what a
“discourse goal” is, nor how it might be caused (these were not among the
goals of the study). Rather, speakers were merely asked to supply “reasons
[for] why an individual might use [a kind of figurative language].” Whether
these “reasons for use” align with other discussions of the array of phenom-
ena falling under the present term pragmatic effects is not yet clear. For dis-
cussion of this issue, consider first the question of what discourse goals or
pragmatic effects actually are. The question of whether there might be prag-
matic effects outside of existing psychological, linguistic, and philosophical
use/comprehension accounts is then taken up afterward.
More important for our purposes was another problem with SAT con-
cerning its general lack of precision regarding how perlocutions would
actually happen in addressees. Portions of this latter problem also were
either never satisfactorily solved (e.g., how does an addressee know which
of several possible perlocutions to choose from or how does the addressee
know when to stop choosing or embellishing perlocutions; see the section
“Relevance Theory” later), or attempted solutions ended up not garnering
empirical support. For example, in the case of indirect or figurative utter-
ances, one solution had addressees conducting multiple comprehensions
(Searle 1975, 1979). First, an initial comprehension would be made that
derived the so-called pure locution of an utterance independent of lexical,
syntactical, and semantic sources of information. A second comprehension
then would take place on realization that the result of the first was incom-
patible with the context at hand. As will be mentioned at multiple points
in this book, this strict two- or multistage model has repeatedly shown a
lack of empirical support as a universal account of indirect or figurative
language comprehension (Gibbs 1994).1
Despite these problems, SAT was nonetheless a groundbreaking account
that attempted to describe the range of meanings that can or must arise in
the mind of a comprehender when encountering an indirect or figurative
utterance. Its notion of a perlocution was an important benchmark in the
research leading to investigations of pragmatic effects.
Gricean Theory
A second theoretical framework that also dealt with pragmatic effects
somewhat directly was the work of philosopher Paul Grice’s on recognized
intentions. Grice attempted to explain a speaker’s making of an indirect
or figurative utterance by arguing that the speaker would do so with an
“m-intention.” M-intentions are intentions that speakers have and want
their addressees to recognize such that the recognition brings about cer-
tain effects in the addressees. For example, imagine a situation in which a
family pet dog named Musket is sitting next to and facing an exterior door.
One family member, Maria, is sitting across the room, and another person,
Simone, enters from a side interior door and passes by the pet. Maria says,
“Musket, do you want to go outside?” (2.3)
In making this utterance, Maria has an m-intention to get Simone to open
the door and let the dog out. It is not just an intention, as in being what
Maria wants to have happen. It is additionally an m-intention because
Defining a Pragmatic Effect 25
Maria also wants Simone to recognize that this is what she wants to have
happen as a means of making it happen.
M-intentions thus in some ways add the qualities of perlocutions to
illocutionary forces. They are effects in addressees (or, technically, in this
example, overhearers) intended on the part of speakers in making their
utterances. These effects require deriving the illocutionary force behind
the locution, but they also go beyond that illocutionary force. Thus, in this
example, not only must Simone derive some meaning out of Maria’s utter-
ance that is broader than the locution (realizing an offer to go outside from
an inquiry on whether the dog has a desire to go outside), but that meaning
also involves a desired effect in Simone. In this case, this involves an action
on his part (to let the dog out).
In somewhat blending perlocutions and illocutionary forces, a further
construct was needed to fill the gap between an addressee deriving the
intended meaning of an utterance and then exhibiting the intended per-
locutionary effects brought from the speaker’s use of that utterance. In this
example, for instance, something is needed to account for how Simone real-
izes that Maria’s utterance is really directing him to open the door. For this,
Grice developed the idea of an implicature. An implicature is an inference
on the part of the addressee, authorized by the speaker, to derive the speak-
er’s m-intention and its consequences to arrive at a final comprehension.
One might first ask why a notion of implicature is necessary when the
idea of an illocutionary force – again, that which the speaker intended to
communicate – is already available. The main problem again is that an illo-
cutionary force, even if expanded to include all that a speaker is authorizing
the addressee to infer, does not supply a mechanism for how the addressee
derives all that meaning. Also, SAT greatly underestimates the interactive
nature of emergent meaning that plays a big role in meaning derivation. As
discussed later, Grice’s framework turns out to also fail at fully fixing these
problems, but it goes much further than SAT did.
For our main purpose here of delineating pragmatic effects, the notion
of an implicature buys a lot of ground. According to Grice’s view, then,
a pragmatic effect could be some meaning, belief, or knowledge that an
addressee (or other kind of comprehender) infers based on a comprehen-
sion of an utterance and a context. To illustrate this with a classic example,
consider the following three characters: Seth is a man who is romantically
attracted to a woman named Aretha, whom he has only seen from afar.
Aretha has a close friend, Min jun, who works with Seth, so Min jun and
Seth are acquainted. One day Seth decides to begin pursuing Aretha, so he
begins by asking Min jun if Aretha is married. Min jun replies,
26 What Is a Pragmatic Effect?
Here no explicit statement about where it is raining is uttered. But the infer-
ence that it is raining in the city where the baseball game is being played is
made possible by the context at hand.
Generalized implicatures, however, are those that can get made inde-
pendent of local contexts. As just one example, consider scalar implicatures
(Bott & Noveck 2004; Carston 1998; De Neys & Schaeken 2007; Levinson
2000; Noveck 2001; Noveck & Posada 2003; Papafragou & Musolino 2003;
Defining a Pragmatic Effect 27
Sperber & Wilson 1986, 1995). These implicatures involve inferences made
on the use of certain quantity terms. For example, if a speaker says,
it is likely that hearers would infer that some of the packages also have not
arrived. Note, though, that such an inference is not logically derived from
what is explicitly stated in the utterance – ”some,” in reference to the pack-
ages that have arrived, does not automatically mean that the remainder of
the packages have not arrived.
Even with these and other elaborations on the idea of implicatures,
however, there remains problems with Grice’s view. The biggest of these
concerns the remaining issue of an implicit claim that multiple sequential
interpretations would be needed for all figurative language comprehension.
This problem is really a leftover from SAT. Indeed, most of the empirical
studies that revealed this problem referred to a blend of Searle’s and Grice’s
accounts with the term standard pragmatic model (Gibbs 1994, 2002; Grice
1975; Searle 1979).
A second problem, though, concerns how one might limit the impli-
catures that a comprehender would make. Grice’s view does not supply a
ready mechanism that would impose such a limit. A speaker interpreting
example (2.5), for instance, might infer appropriately that it is raining in the
city where the game is being played. But there is nothing to stop further
inferences, such as therefore the game is canceled, therefore the visit invita-
tion is rescinded, therefore I am no longer welcome, therefore I must leave
now, and so on. There is no mechanism that allows for selection of which of
these possible inferences the speaker intended the interpreter to draw, nor
for a stop to drawing inferences. Clearly, except when people are suffering
from paranoia, they do not generate inferences into infinity. They also seem
readily able under normal circumstances to arrive at a set of inferences that,
if not exactly what the speaker intended, seems to nonetheless approximate
those intentions, allowing the conversation to proceed successfully. The
next account attempted solutions to both these problems.
Relevance Theory
The third theoretical approach that deals explicitly with pragmatic effects
is relevance theory (Goatly 1997; Hanna 2011; Kovecses 2011; Schourup
2011; Sperber & Wilson 1986, 1995; White 2011; Wilson 2011; Wilson &
Sperber 2012). According to the basic tenets of relevance theory, language
28 What Is a Pragmatic Effect?
and
Where relevance theory and the principle of optimal relevance really pay
off, though, is when utterances do not seem to apply directly to the current
set of contextual assumptions. In such cases, comprehenders are warranted
to compute positive cognitive effects that bring in additional meaning.
Consider the same situation with the new response utterance, “A root
canal,” in the following3:
[A description is expected] + [a negative description is expected] + [“A
root canal”] = PCgE – getting a root canal is a particularly bad experience;
PCgE – the experience of watching the game was similar to the experi-
ence of getting a root canal; PCgE – watching the game was a particularly
bad experience; PCgE – confirmation of expectation of description; and
PCgE – confirmation of expectation of negative description. (2.11)
In these situations, the kinds of positive cognitive effects that bring in addi-
tional meaning are very similar to conversational implicatures in Grice’s
view. But what relevance theory additionally supplies is contained in the
more complex sense of optimal relevance that allows selection among pos-
sible positive cognitive effects, as well as a means of limiting them. Optimal
relevance here essentially means that (1) there is additional meaning that
the speaker wants the comprehender to infer, (2) computing this additional
meaning is worth the comprehender’s effort (i.e., it is not just superfluous),
(3) this meaning fits with what the comprehender can and would prefer
to infer, and (4) once there is enough additional meaning inferred to jus-
tify the effort to infer it, the comprehender can stop inferring additional
information.
Relevance theory thus does a better job with the problems described ear-
lier concerning Grice’s view. Relevance theory, through optimal relevance,
allows for selection of appropriate positive cognitive effects (one type of
pragmatic effects in present terms). Relevance theory, or at least some inter-
pretations of it, also diminishes the implicit claim that figurative or indirect
language requires multiple stages of comprehension relative to direct lan-
guage that requires only one. In relevance-theoretic terms, all utterances (or
at least most), direct and indirect, require computation of positive cognitive
effects. Some utterances might license the computation of a greater quantity
or greater complexity of positive cognitive effects, but nearly all utterances
will require at least some such computations.
Relevance theory, building on the accounts leading up to it, has emerged
as the “juggernaut” of pragmatic explanations of meaning derivation (Gibbs
2005). The enormous attention it has received demonstrates the power of
some of its ideas, as well as the passionate criticism the ideas have invoked,
30 What Is a Pragmatic Effect?
leading to its ongoing revision. For instance, its application to the compre-
hension of metaphors and the tradeoff that arises between cognitive effort
and the computation of positive cognitive effects, as well as how those might
be predicted and measured, are current topics of much discussion (Carston &
Wearing 2011; Gibbs & Tendahl 2006, 2011; Gil 2011; Kovecses 2011; Ryder &
Leinonen 2011, 2014; Schourup 2011; Sequeiros 2011; Tendahl & Gibbs 2008;
Walaszewska 2011; White 2011; Wilson 2011). As will also be shown later,
how relevance theory might handle different depths of pragmatic effects –
ranging from those inherent in the structure of a trope, through those that
might be embodied, up to those that might involve social and cultural in
addition to cognitive processes – is also unclear. However, as one of the lat-
est and very widely studied, debated, and considered attempts to corral the
notion of pragmatic effects and how they might be addressed with relatively
parsimonious principles, relevance theory has made a major impact.
Philosophical Accounts
Other important linguistic/philosophic accounts also provide in-depth
bases for discussing different pragmatic effect accomplishments (e.g.,
Recanati 2004, 2007). Consider as just one example Dascal’s (2003) des-
ignation between “comprehended” and “grasped” meaning. According to
this view, all kinds of speaker comprehension involve the use of pragmatics
either to confirm that an explicitly stated meaning is intended by the speaker
or to invoke an inferential abductive process to create interpretive hypoth-
eses that reveal implicit meanings of the speaker. These hypotheses in the
latter case could entail beliefs very similar to implicatures in the Gricean
account. In either case, though, such comprehension can take place while
still leaving out deeper meaningful aspects of the conversation intended by
the speaker or inherent in the conversation based on the speaker’s talk or
behavior. To achieve these deeper meanings, the hearer must additionally
“grasp” the speaker’s meaning beyond mere “comprehension.”
As an illustration, imagine that a medical patient and his physician are
talking about the high cost of Alzheimer’s medications, perhaps stemming
casually from their noting that they had both viewed a recent television
advertisement for a memory-enhancement drug. The conversation might
be drastically different, though, if the doctor knew that her patient’s mother
was suffering from the disease relative to the doctor not knowing this. The
potentially deeper meaning of the patient’s seemingly idle input into the dis-
cussion of the drug, when his mother is in fact ill with Alzheimer’s, and the
doctor’s grasping of this depth could involve more profound and important
Defining a Pragmatic Effect 31
kinds of hypotheses generated on the doctor’s part. These could affect the
train, comprehension, and appropriateness of the rest of the conversation.
As will be discussed at various points later, this comprehension/grasp-
ing distinction, along with other rich psychological phenomena that occur
in human interactions, could underlie the performance of a number of
pragmatic effects (e.g., ingratiation, mastery display, and admiration; see
Chapter 3). These effects might not currently fall within the explanatory
shadow of current accounts. That the doctor might derive these additional
effects in the case where the patient’s mother is known to be ill, for instance,
is not just triggered by that propositional knowledge. It also arises from a
deeply emotional and empathetic response, very much under the umbrella
of broader psychological influences on language comprehension, that may
not reside exclusively within that comprehension yet still affect it.
Inferences
In addition to the theoretical linguistic and philosophical work that has
progressively refined concepts similar to pragmatic effects, another source
of ideas about pragmatic effects is the more quantitative empirical and
experimental work predominantly in psycholinguistics on inferences.4
This is a rather large body of work extending over several decades that has
attempted to empirically identify what kinds of meanings readers/hearers
get more or less directly out of texts versus deriving or inferring from those
texts during the process of online language processing. Major goals of this
work have been to identify (1) what kinds of inferences are drawn, (2) when
are they drawn (e.g., immediately on reading/hearing some text/talk con-
struction or at some point later), (3) which inferences are necessary versus
more optionally elaborative, and (4) what kinds of orienting tasks might
affect whether different kinds of inferences are drawn and when?
A full review of this literature is far beyond the scope of this chapter,
particularly the immense methodological issues and concerns in this work.5
Indeed, these methodological concerns leave definitive answers to the pre-
ceding questions as yet unavailable and arguably impossible given current
technologies despite recent developments in eye-tracking and virtual-world
paradigms. Nevertheless, several of these kinds of inferences might be simi-
lar to the pragmatic effects discussed here for figurative or indirect lan-
guage. Among these are the general categories of coherence and elaborative
inferences – respectively, the concern inferences that are argued as nec-
essary for a given construction to provide a coherent comprehension and
inferences that are not as strictly necessary but which may nonetheless be
32 What Is a Pragmatic Effect?
and as part of the figures themselves as in proverbs or verbal irony such as,
A great deal of debate has taken place between some linguistic and phil-
osophical accounts concerning the role of contextual information in index-
ical and later processing. These debates apply here to coherence inferences
in figurative language. For example, is it the case that the referential assign-
ment of “it” to “room” must happen for the metaphor comprehension to
succeed in (2.12)? Some accounts would argue for such a necessity, at least
for novel metaphors. Others might hold that the contextual momentum of
(2.12) being used in an actual setting of a filthy room may diminish refer-
ential assignment necessity for full metaphoric comprehension. Indeed, a
hearer could potentially miss hearing the “it’s an” part altogether and still
telegraphically make the assignment and comprehend the metaphor.
Other accounts grapple with the level of fixedness apparent in compa-
rable utterances and how that affects indexical processing. Consider the ref-
erential assignment of “its” in (2.13) versus (2.14). Example (2.14), in being
a much more familiar and widely used proverb, might benefit from its con-
current greater fixedness. The referential assignment may be less of a neces-
sity accordingly. Whether a pronominal referent is context independent or
dependent is also important at both “said” and “conveyed” levels of mean-
ing (Recanati 2004). Compare the referential assignments of (2.15) and
(2.16) at each of these meaning levels. In (2.16), the referential assignment is
neatly contained in the proverb – “they” refers to “things. In (2.15), however,
the referential assignment is external in both uses of “they.” Finally, con-
sider the complexities of referential assignments across different figures in
Random documents with unrelated
content Scribd suggests to you:
BERKELEY CASTLE.
Berkeley has another claim to distinction aside from its castle, for
here is the cottage where lived Jenner, whose discovery of
vaccination placed under control the scourge that devastated Europe
until quite recent times. The famous physician is buried in the
churchyard. The church is of imposing dimensions, with stained
glass better than the average and elaborate tombs of the Lords of
Berkeley Castle. The bell tower is detached, standing some distance
from the main structure.
The highway from Bristol to Gloucester is one of the finest in the
Kingdom, and we soon resumed our flight over it after the short
detour to Berkeley. At the Bell Hotel in Gloucester we found mild
excitement prevailing among the guests and servants, some of the
latter standing about in brilliant liveries and powdered wigs. The
manageress explained that the high sheriff and county judge were
about to leave the hotel and that the gaudy attire we beheld
disguised only the porter and head waiter, who had been fitted out
in this manner to give due state to the occasion. During the delay in
the departure of the distinguished guests we had the services of one
of the gorgeous gentlemen at our luncheon. Finally the dignitaries
descended the stair, the bedecked servants bowed them solemnly
into a carriage, and the porter in all his glory rode away beside the
driver. I dwell on this incident, trifling in itself, to illustrate the
different status of such officials in England as compared with our
own country. In America a dozen county judges and sheriffs might
be at a hotel in a city the size of Gloucester without attracting much
attention. In some respects the English way is preferable, since it
invests the representatives of the law with a dignity quite lacking in
the States. And in this connection we might notice that county
judges in England receive salaries from three to five times as great
as are paid to corresponding officials on our side, thus commanding
a high average of legal talent for the bench.
The half-dozen miles between Gloucester and Tewkesbury are
quickly done and we halt in front of a wide green, studded with
gigantic trees, amidst which rises the huge bulk of a church almost
as imposing as the cathedral that has barely faded from our view.
But it lacks the gracefulness and perfect proportion of the Gloucester
church and perhaps its most striking exterior feature is the arch over
the western windows, so high and majestic as to remind one of
Peterborough. The interior is mainly ponderous Norman—rows of
heavy pillars flanking the long nave and supporting massive rounded
arches. The windows, however, are the lighter and more graceful
creations of the Decorated Period, though the glass is mostly
modern. Among the tombs is that of Prince Edward, son of Henry
VI., who was cruelly slain in the battle of Tewkesbury, so fatal to the
Lancastrian cause. Here, too, lies the “false, fleeting, perjured
Clarence,” of Shakespeare; and Somerset, executed by his captors
after the battle. The abbey was marked for destruction by Henry
VIII., who was deterred from his purpose by a public subscription.
Tewkesbury is rather decadent, and has many houses in brick and
timber as yet quite unspoiled by modern improvement. It is
pleasantly situated on the banks of the classic Avon near its junction
with the Severn, and the many-arched stone bridge over the former
river is unusually picturesque. Half a mile farther a second bridge
crosses the Severn, which lies in broad, still reaches dotted with
small craft of every description.
Over these bridges we hastened away toward Hereford, following a
level though sinuous road. The old-world quaintness of Ledbury
attracted our attention. Its rectangular timber market cross,
supported on a colonnade of wooden pillars, is unusual indeed. And
nowhere else did we find finer specimens of Elizabethan half-
timbered houses, though some of them were rather tawdry in recent
applications of black and white paint. Such houses have become
quite the rage and some owners have gone so far as to paint black
stripes on common brick to represent the timbers. However, no such
travesty as this is necessary in Ledbury—the town is overflowing
with the genuine article—genuine though disfigured in some cases
by the bad taste of the man with the paint pot. Church Lane, leading
from the main street up a gentle slope to the church, is bordered
with splendid examples of Elizabethan houses, quite unaltered since
they left the builders’ hands. At the end of the lane one sees a
graceful spire standing apart from the church, which is quite unique
in design. It has four sharply pitched roofs running parallel, with odd
little minarets between them. The interior has the newness of recent
restoration and shows traces of different styles, from Norman to
Perpendicular. Ledbury has an institute which commemorates its
association with Elizabeth Barrett Browning, who passed her girlhood
near the town.
At Hereford we sought the cathedral, having missed the interior
during a former visit. A small, bare-headed boy in a red sweater saw
us pause before the close and marked us as his legitimate prey. “I’ll
take you into the Bishop’s Palace,” he said in such a matter-of-fact
way that it disarmed our suspicions and we followed the youngster
meekly enough, for with all our doing of cathedrals we had caught
only glimpses of bishops’ palaces, usually embowered in gardens
and apparently quite inaccessible. We had no opportunity to
question our small guide as he rapidly led us through the palace
grounds, but when he unhesitatingly rang at the door, we insisted on
an explanation and learned that the bishop and his family were in
London. During their absence the palace was thrown open to the
public and our small friend was doubtless improving the opportunity
to put cathedral visitors under obligations to himself.
We were admitted and wandered about at will. It is a rambling old
house and indicates that a bishop occupies about the same plane in
his domestic appointments as a prosperous member of the nobility,
among whom, in fact, he takes a high rank. The house was
sumptuously furnished and had several great rooms with high
decorated ceilings and windows that looked out on the pleasant
grounds, bright with flowers and shrubbery. The study pleased us
most, with its high bookshelves about the walls and tall mullioned
bow windows which open almost directly on the Wye. It was easy to
see why the English bishops nearly all complain that their salaries,
though apparently large, are hardly adequate to the state they are
expected to maintain; and why, as in the case of an American
ambassador, a private fortune is often necessary to enable the
recipient of such an honor to pay the legitimate expenses. Our
picture will show, perhaps better than any description, the beauty of
the river front of the palace, with the fine trees and cathedral tower
in the background. We had only a moment to look about the
cathedral, since the closing hour was nearly at hand. However, we
missed little, for Hereford Cathedral has few historic associations and
recent restoration gives it an almost new appearance. It is built of
red sandstone, which gives the interior a rather warm tone,
accentuated by highly-colored modern windows.
BISHOP’S PALACE, HEREFORD.
A pause for the night at Ludlow, where we arrived after a run of an
hour or two through the rich pasture lands along the Welsh Border,
gave us an opportunity of renewing our pleasant associations with
that fine old town. But as we were to visit Ludlow thrice before the
close of our pilgrimage, I shall leave our impressions and discoveries
for later consideration.
The road from Ludlow to Bridgnorth is—or rather was—not a first-
class one. Road conditions in Britain change so rapidly since the
advent of the motor that one can scarcely speak of them in the
present tense. As we found it, poorly surfaced, narrow and winding,
it was not to be compared with the highway along the border.
Bridgnorth is an ancient market town, famous for its cattle fair,
which has been held yearly since 1226. The service at the Crown
Inn, where we stopped for luncheon, was excellent, and the
moderate charge proved Bridgnorth off the beaten tourist track, a
special rate not yet being established for the infrequent motorists. It
was market day and the town was crowded with country people. The
ample market square was filled with booths, and goods of every
description were offered for sale. A socialist orator—a common
nuisance in England—was haranguing the people, who crowded the
streets so closely that we could get through only with difficulty. That
motors are not so common in Bridgnorth was apparent, and a crowd
collected about the car in the hotel stableyard. The general
expression was hostile, and many instances were related where “one
of the things” had worked disaster with skittish horses.
We made our escape without entering into the discussion and
dropped down the almost precipitous hill to the Severn bridge. The
road is a charming one, with wooded hills rising sharply on one hand
and the broad Severn lying far beneath on the other. At Shifnal a
policeman, in response to our inquiry, directed us to the byway
leading to the village of Tong, some three miles distant. Here,
according to one well qualified to judge, is the “most interesting
example of early Perpendicular architecture in Shropshire—a section
famous for interesting churches.” But it is better known through its
association with Little Nell in “Old Curiosity Shop,” and Dickens’
description shows that the appearance of the church before its
restoration was quite different from today:
“The church was old and grey, with ivy clinging to the walls and
round the porch. It was a very quiet place, as such a place should
be, save for the cawing of the rooks, who had built their nests
among the branches of some tall trees. It was a very aged, ghostly
place. The church had been built many hundreds of years ago and
once had a convent or monastery attached; for arches in ruins,
remains of oriel windows, and fragments of blackened walls were yet
standing.” It is still old and gray, but no longer ghostly and ruinous.
It was far from lonely, for a crowd of trippers was being shown
about by the caretaker when we arrived.
The tombs of Tong Church, with their effigies and brasses, are
remarkably perfect, and one of them must be very ancient, for it
bears the figure of a crusader in chain mail. The images escaped
destruction, it is said, because of the friendship of Cromwell for the
Stanleys, who were adherents of the Parliament. In the church are
buried several of the Vernons, whom the madcap Dorothy gave to
eternal fame, for they had little else to rescue them from the
oblivion that overwhelmed such a host of unremembered squires
and knights. Dorothy’s sister, Margaret, is buried with her husband,
Sir Edward Stanley, who came into possession of Tong Castle
through his wife. The church also has a remarkable library of black-
letter books, some of them almost as old as the church itself, and a
stupendous bell, weighing two tons, hangs in its tower.
CARDIFF CASTLE.
Cardiff’s municipal buildings are a delight; white stone palaces
standing in ample grounds with wide pleasant approaches—
altogether models of what civic structures ought to be. Immense
and busy as it is, there is little in Cardiff to detain one on such a
pilgrimage as ours, and we were away before noon on the Swansea
road.
Llandaff is but three miles from Cardiff, and we reached it by a short
detour. Its cathedral, recently restored, is probably the most
interesting of Welsh churches excepting St. David’s. The site has
been occupied by a church ever since the year 600, though the
present structure dates from early Norman times. It fell into
complete ruin after the time of the Commonwealth. One chronicler
declares that “Cromwell’s men turned the nave into an ale house,
penned calves in the choir and fed pigs at the font,” though they
must have been rather unorthodox Puritans to countenance the ale
house. No attempt was made to preserve the fine church from decay
until about two hundred years later, and so deplorable was its
condition that the task of restoration seemed a well-nigh impossible
one. Still, after much difficulty, the work was happily carried out, and
the twin towers—one a slender spire and its companion square-
topped with Gothic finials—present a very unusual though not
unpleasant effect. Inside there is a mixture of Norman and early
English styles, and some beautiful Decorated work. There are three
paintings by Dante Gabriel Rossetti that arrest attention at once—
done in that artist’s best style long ere he was known to fame. The
windows, though modern, are of unusual excellence, having been
designed by Burne-Jones and other notable artists. Near by are the
ruins of the bishop’s palace, whose fortresslike walls tell of a time
when the churchman and the warrior went hand in hand. Its
destruction some six hundred years ago is attributed to Owen
Glendwr, whose record for castle-smashing in Wales is second only
to that of Cromwell. The village of Llandaff is still rural and pretty; it
is quite clear of the skirts of Cardiff, being separated from the city by
the River Taff. The old stone cross still stands in front of the palace
and there is now little to remind one of the big modern city near at
hand, which may one day absorb its ancient but diminutive neighbor.
The Swansea road looks well enough on the map, but our
recollections of it are far from pleasing. Dusty and rough, and
crowded with traffic and tram lines in many places, it wends through
a cheerless and often uninteresting country. It passes frequent
mining towns straggling along for considerable distances and there
were many drunken men reeling on the streets. It was market day at
Cowbridge and the village was filled with countrymen, many of
whom treated our right to the road with supreme indifference. One
fellow in a broad-brimmed slouch hat that made him look like an
American cowboy, and who was carrying a black bottle that might
hold a gallon, saluted us with owl-like gravity and brought the car to
a sharp stop by standing directly in our way.
While getting rid of our would-be acquaintance, we cast about to
find a place for luncheon and soon lighted on the sign of the Bear,
the sole inn, according to Baedeker. It was some distance to the
next town and we decided to patronize the Bear, though its outer
appearance filled us with misgivings. But if its outward aspect
inspired doubt, words fail in speaking of the inside. The handbook of
the Royal Automobile Club in setting forth the delights of a tour in
America pays its compliments to our rural Bonifaces in this wise:
“The hotel accommodation in country districts is often very poor and
dirty,” all of which may be painfully true. But in competition for
distinction in these particulars, the Bear would certainly not be
distanced by any American rival. Perhaps the confusion and disarray
was partly due to the market-day rush, but the grime and dirt that
prevailed everywhere seemed as ancient as the ramshackle old
house itself. The dining-room was a large apartment with many long
tables of boards laid on trestles—an arrangement, no doubt, to
accommodate the patronage of market day—and the remnants of
the dinner were still heaped upon them in dire confusion. A glance
at the meal placed before us and at the dirty hands of the waiting-
girl was enough—we left the provender untouched and summarily
departed from the table. With difficulty we got the attention of the
barmaid, who also acted as cashier, settled our score, and sallied
forth dinnerless upon the King’s highway.
Threading our way carefully through the streets of Neath, several
miles farther on, with little thought save to get away from the bad
road and unpleasant surroundings, we caught a glimpse, down a
side street, of an ivy-clad ruin of great extent. We followed the
rough rubbish-covered lane that leads directly to the entrance gate
of Neath Abbey, as it proved to be. There was no caretaker in
charge, but two or three workmen were engaged in cleaning away
the debris, which was several feet deep in many of the roofless
apartments. Everything indicated that once the abbey had stood in
the pleasantest of valleys on the bank of a clear, placid little river;
but the coaling industry, which flings its pall over everything in
Southern Wales, had played sad havoc with the sylvan retreat of the
old Cistercian monks. Heaps of rubbish dotted the uncared-for green
about the place. Coal trains rattled on the railroad near at hand. The
spot where the abbey now stands so forlornly is the heart of the
suburban slums of Neath, and so isolated and forgotten is it that few
pilgrims come to view its melancholy beauty. For it is beautiful—does
not our picture tell the story?—the mouldering walls hung with
masses of ivy, the fine doorways, the great groups of mullioned
windows and the high chimneys, green to the very tops, all combine
to charm the beholder despite the unlovely surroundings. The
workmen told us that the abbey belonged to Lord Somebody—we
have quite forgotten—and that he was going to clean up the
premises and make necessary repairs. The craze now so prevalent in
Britain for preserving every ancient ruin had extended even to Neath
Abbey and perchance its titled owner will beautify the surroundings
and the fine ruin may yet become a shrine for pilgrims—that the
motor-car will bring.
NEATH ABBEY, SOUTH WALES.
Swansea—Swansy, they call it—had always brought to my mind, I
hardly know why, the idea of a seaside resort town; but never was
preconceived notion more erroneous. If there is a blacker, uglier,
more odoriferous town of the size in the Kingdom, I do not recollect
where it is. Here are the greatest copper smelting works in the world
and from these come the pungent, stifling odors that so
unpleasantly pervade the city. Here, too, is the great steel plant of
the Siemens Company and many allied industries. And yet there was
a time when Swansea had at least the promise of a resort town
before it, when the poet Landor declared that “Italy has a fine
climate but that of Swansea is better; that it is the only spot in
Britain where one may have warmth without wet.” Then it had six
hundred people, but now its population exceeds one hundred
thousand. We had no desire to linger and rapidly climbed the long
steep hill that leads to the highland road to Carmarthen. We soon
left behind us the smoke and grime of the collieries and smelting-
works, and the road over which we rapidly coursed took us through
a rather pretty rural section, though the hills are numerous and
steep.
It was late when we came into Carmarthen, a bare, drab-colored
town, but withal rather more prosperous-looking than the average
small town of South Wales. The thirty-two miles to Haverfordwest
swept by too rapidly to permit us to see the country other than as a
fleeting panorama. Just as the twilight faded into dark we came
sharply into Haverfordwest and with grave misgivings halted at the
Castle Hotel. Here we must stop, willy nilly, for there was nothing
that promised better in many miles. But to apply the cautious
Yorkshireman’s expression to the Castle Hotel, “It might be worse,”
and we were willing to let the uncomfortable feather-beds and the
dingy candle-lit rooms overlooking the stable yard, be atoned for by
the excellent dinner that our landlady prepared at so late an hour.
We did not linger at Haverfordwest on the following morning, though
perhaps the castle and the priory church might well have detained
us. The castle, which crowns the terribly steep hill to which the town
seems to cling somewhat precariously, has been reduced to a county
jail—or gaol, as the English have it—and thus robbed of much of its
romance. Still, it is an impressive old fortress, dominating the town
with its huge bulk, and it has figured much in the annals of
Pembrokeshire.
Haverfordwest has a history antedating the Conquest. It was
undoubtedly a stopping-place for the troops of pilgrims who in early
days journeyed to the sacred shrine of St. David’s, the Ultima Thule
of Southern Wales, sixteen miles to the west, following a tortuous
road over many steep and barren hills. The railroad ends at
Haverfordwest and no doubt the facilities for reaching St. David’s a
thousand years ago were quite as good as today, the daily mail cart
and coach twice a week in season being the only regular means of
transportation. No wonder in days when strenuous journeys to
distant shrines were believed to be especially meritorious, two trips
to St. David’s were allowed to confer the spiritual benefit of a single
pilgrimage to Rome itself.
And we ourselves are pilgrims to St. David’s shrine—not by the slow
horseback cavalcade of old days, or the more modern coach, but by
motor car. Our forty-horse engine makes quick work of the
precipitous hill out of Haverfordwest and carries us without lagging
over the dozen long steep hills on the road to the ancient town.
Shortly before reaching St. David’s the road drops down to the
ocean side, but the sea is hidden by a long ridge of stones and
pebbles piled high by the inrushing waters. The tide was far out and
we saw no finer beach on the Welsh coast than the one that lay
before us as we stood on the stony drift. A great expanse of yellow
—almost literally golden—sand ran down to a pale green sea, which
lapped it in silvery sunlit ripples, so quiet and peaceful was the day.
But one could not but think of the scope afforded for the wild play of
the ocean on stormy days—how the scene must be beyond all
description
We left the car near the ancient stone cross in the deserted market
place of St. David’s and sought the cathedral, which is strangely
situated in a deep dell, the top of the Norman tower being only a
little above the level of the market place. The cathedral has been
recently restored, more perhaps on account of its historic past than
any present need for it, but the bishop’s palace, once one of the
most elaborate and extensive in the Kingdom, stands in picturesque
decay, beyond any hope of rehabilitation. As to the old-time
importance of St. David’s as contrasted with its present isolation, the
words of an enthusiastic English writer may perhaps serve better
than my own:
“Centuries ago St. David’s bishop had seven palaces for his pleasure;
now he does not dwell in his own city. Of old the offerings at St.
David’s shrine were divided every Saturday among the priests by the
dishful, to save time in counting the coins; now a few pounds weekly
is accounted a good collection total. Ancient kings came hither in
state to confess their sins; in this travelling age only the enterprising
tourist comes to the city at all. Eight or nine roads converged upon
the little place on its headland of about three miles square, but the
majority are now no better than humble weather-worn lanes. The
Atlantic winds sweep across the depression by the Alan brook in
which St. David’s Cathedral, the extensive ruins of the bishop’s
palace, and the many other fragments of St. David’s glorious prime
nestle among trees, with the humble cottages of the city itself
surrounding them as if they loved them. Even the dilapidation here
is so graceful that one would hardly wish it altered into the trim and
rather smug completeness of many an English cathedral with its
close.”
The cathedral is extremely interesting and made doubly so by an
intelligent verger whom we located with considerable difficulty.
Pilgrims to St. David’s were apparently too infrequent to justify the
good man’s remaining constantly on duty as in larger places, and a
placard forbidding fees, may have dampened his zeal in looking for
visitors. But we found him at last in his garden, and he did his part
well; nothing curious or important in the history of the cathedral was
forgotten by him. The leaning Norman pillars, the open roof of Irish
oak, the gorgeous ceiling with its blood-red and gold decorations,
and many relics discovered during the restoration, were pointed out
and properly descanted upon. But one might write volumes of a
shrine which kings once underwent many hardships to visit, among
them Harold the Saxon and his conqueror, William of Normandy.
Nothing but a visit can do it justice, and with the advent of the
motor car, old St. David’s will again be the shrine of an increasing
number of pilgrims, though their mission and personel be widely
different from the wayfarers of early days.
ST. DAVID’S CATHEDRAL.
There is only one road out of the lonely little town besides that
which brought us thither and we were soon upon the stony and
uncomfortable highway to Cardigan. Here we found roadmaking in
primitive stages; the broken stone had been loosely scattered along
the way waiting for the heavy-wheeled carts of the farmers to serve
the purpose of the steam roller. The country is pitifully barren and
the little hovels—always gleaming with whitewash—were later called
to mind by those in Ireland. There are no great parks with fine
mansions to relieve the monotony of the scene. Only fugitive
glimpses of the ocean from the upland road occasionally lend a
touch of variety. At Fishguard, a mean little town with a future
before it—for it is now the Welsh terminus of the Great Western
Railway’s route to Ireland—we paused in the crowded market square
and a courteous policeman approached us, divining that we needed
directions.
“The road to Cardigan? Straight ahead down the hill.”
“It looks pretty steep,” we suggested.
“Yes, but nothing to the one you must go up out of the town. Just
like the roofs of those houses there, and the road rough and
crooked. Yes, this is all there is of Fishguard; pretty quiet place
except on market days.”
We thanked the officer and cautiously descended the hill before us.
We then climbed much the steepest and most dangerous hill we
found in all the twelve thousand or more miles covered by our
wanderings. To our dismay, a grocer’s cart across the narrow road
compelled us to stop midway on the precipitous ascent, but the
motor proved equal to the task and we soon looked back down the
frightful declivity with a sigh of relief. We were told later of a
traveling showman who had been over all the main roads of the
Island with a traction engine and who declared this the worst hill he
knew of.
Newport—quite different from the Eastern Welsh Newport—and
Cardigan are quaint, old-world villages, though now decayed and
shrunken. I will not write of them, though the history of each is lost
in the mists of antiquity and the former possesses an imposing
though ruinous castle. The road between them is hilly, but the hills
are well wooded and the prospects often magnificent and far-
reaching. We found it much the same after leaving Cardigan, though
the country is distinctly better and more pleasing than the extreme
south. The farm houses appear more prosperous, and well-cared-for
gardens surround them. Nowhere did we find the people kinder or
more courteous. An instance occurred at Carmarthen, where we
stopped to consult our maps. The owner of a near-by jewelry shop
came out and accosted us. Did we want information about the
roads? He had lived in Carmarthen many years and was familiar with
all the roads about the town. To Llandovery? We had come too far;
the road north of the river is the best and one of the prettiest in
Wales. It would be worth our while to go back a mile and take this
road.
Thanking him, we retraced our way through the long main street of
the town and were soon away over one of the most perfect and
beautiful of Welsh highways. It runs in straight broad stretches
between rows of fine trees, past comfortable-looking farm houses,
and through cozy little hamlets nestling amid trees and shrubbery,
and seems constantly to increase in charm until it takes one into
Llandovery, twenty-five miles from Carmarthen and the center of one
of the most picturesque sections of Wales.
Lying among wooded hills in a valley where two clear little rivers join
their waters, Llandovery—the church among the waters—is a village
of surpassing loveliness. The touch of antiquity so necessary to
complete the charm is in the merest fragment of its castle, a
mouldering bit of wall on a mound overlooking the rivers—
dismantled “by Cromwell’s orders.” Delightful as the town is, its
surroundings are even more romantic. The highest peaks of South
Wales, the Beacon and the Black Mountains, overlook it and in the
recesses of these rugged hills are many resorts for the fisherman
and summer excursionist. From the summits are vast panoramas of
wooded hills and verdant valleys. The view is so far-reaching that on
a clear day one may see the ocean to the south; or, far distant in the
opposite direction, the snow-crowned mountains of Northern Wales.
The road from Llandovery to Brecon is as fine as that to Carmarthen,
though it is more sinuous and hilly. But it is perfectly surfaced and
climbs the hills in such long sweeping curves and easy uniform
grades that the steepest scarcely checks the flight of our car as it
hastens at a thirty-five mile gait to Brecon. It is growing late—we
might well wish for more time to admire the views from the hillside
road. The valleys are shrouded in the purple haze of twilight and the
sky is rich with sunset coloring. It has been a strenuous day for us—
one of our longest runs over much bad road. We note with
satisfaction the promise of a first-class hotel at Brecon, though we
find it crowded almost to our exclusion. But we are so weary that we
vigorously protest and a little shifting—with some complaint from the
shifted parties—makes room for us. We are told in awe-stricken
whispers that the congestion is partly due to the fact that Her Grace
the Duchess of B—— (wife of one of the richest peers in England)
has arrived at the hotel with her retinue, traveling in two motor cars.
She was pointed out to us in the morning as she walked along the
promenade in very short skirts, accompanied by her poodle. We
heard of this duke often in our journeyings, one old caretaker in a
place owned by the nobleman assuring us that his income was no
less than a guinea a minute! The duke owns many blocks of
buildings in some of the busiest sections of London. The land
occupied by them came into possession of the family through the
marriage of the great-grandfather of the present holder of the title
with the daughter of a dairy farmer who owned much of the quarter
where London real estate is now of fabulous value—thus showing
that some of the English aristocracy rose to wealth by means quite
as plebeian as some of those across the water. Nowadays the
penniless duke would have crossed the Atlantic to recoup his
fortune, instead of turning to a rich dairyman’s daughter in his own
country.
But in indulging in this more or less interesting gossip, I am
forgetting Brecon and the Castle Hotel, rightly named in this
instance, for the hotel owns the old castle; it stands in the private
grounds which lie between the hotel and the river and are beautified
with flowers and shrubbery. Brecon boasts of great antiquity and it
was here that Sir John Price made overtures to Henry VIII. which
resulted in the union of England and Wales. The priory church is one
of the largest and most important in Wales and is interesting in
architecture as well as historical association. We saw the plain old
house where the ever-charming Mrs. Siddons was born—a distinction
of which Brecon is justly proud. And Brecon is not without its legend
of Charles the Wanderer, who passed a day or two at the priory
during one of his hurried marches in Wales, and the letter he wrote
here is the first record we have of his despair of the success of the
royal cause.
My chapter is already too long—but what else might be expected of
an effort to crowd into a few pages the record of sights and
impressions that might well fill a volume?
VIII
SOME NOOKS AND CORNERS
Early next day we were in Hereford, for it is but forty miles from
Brecon by the Wye Valley road. It had been just one week since we
had passed through the town preparatory to our tour of South Wales
—a rather wearisome journey of well upon a thousand miles over
some of the worst of Welsh roads. It was not strange, then, that we
gladly seized the opportunity for a short rest in Hereford. There is
something fascinating about the fine old cathedral town. It appeals
to one as a place of repose and quiet, though this may be apparent
rather than real, for we found the Green Dragon filled to the point of
turning away would-be guests. The town stands sedately in the
midst of the broad, level meadows which surround it on every side,
and through its very center meanders the Wye, the queenliest of
British rivers, as though loath to leave the confines of such a
pleasant place. It is a modern city, despite its ancient history, for its
old-time landmarks have largely disappeared and its crowded lanes
have been superseded by broad streets. Even the cathedral has a
distressingly new appearance, due to the recent restoration, and a
public park occupies the site of the vanished castle. But for all that,
one likes Hereford. Its newness is not the cheap veneer so
frequently evident in the resort towns; it is solid and genuine
throughout and there are enough antique corners to redeem it from
monotony. To sum up our impressions, Hereford is a place one
would gladly visit again—and again.
Jotted down on our map adjacent to the Tewkesbury road were blue
crosses, indicating several seldom-visited nooks and corners we had
learned of in our reading and which we determined to explore. No
recollection of our wanderings comes back to us rosier with romance
or more freighted with the spirit of rural England than that of our
Welcome to our website – the perfect destination for book lovers and
knowledge seekers. We believe that every book holds a new world,
offering opportunities for learning, discovery, and personal growth.
That’s why we are dedicated to bringing you a diverse collection of
books, ranging from classic literature and specialized publications to
self-development guides and children's books.
ebookbell.com