Engineering Mathematics With MATLAB 1st Edition Won Y. Yang All Chapters Instant Download
Engineering Mathematics With MATLAB 1st Edition Won Y. Yang All Chapters Instant Download
com
https://textbookfull.com/product/engineering-
mathematics-with-matlab-1st-edition-won-y-yang/
https://textbookfull.com/product/multiphysics-modeling-with-
application-to-biomedical-engineering-1st-edition-z-yang/
textbookfull.com
https://textbookfull.com/product/chemical-engineering-computation-
with-matlab-2nd-edition-yeong-koo-yeo/
textbookfull.com
https://textbookfull.com/product/programming-mathematics-using-
matlab-1st-edition-lisa-a-oberbroeckling/
textbookfull.com
https://textbookfull.com/product/assumptions-of-the-tea-party-
movement-a-world-of-their-own-1st-edition-david-warfield-brown-auth/
textbookfull.com
Was revolution inevitable? : turning points of the Russian
Revolution 1st Edition Brenton
https://textbookfull.com/product/was-revolution-inevitable-turning-
points-of-the-russian-revolution-1st-edition-brenton/
textbookfull.com
https://textbookfull.com/product/the-play-of-allusion-in-the-historia-
augusta-1st-edition-david-rohrbacher/
textbookfull.com
https://textbookfull.com/product/translation-and-translanguaging-1st-
edition-mike-baynham-tong-king-lee/
textbookfull.com
https://textbookfull.com/product/the-us-culture-wars-and-the-anglo-
american-special-relationship-david-g-haglund/
textbookfull.com
The Runner s Guide to Healthy Feet and Ankles Simple Steps
to Prevent Injury and Run Stronger 1st Edition Dr. Brian
W. Fullem
https://textbookfull.com/product/the-runner-s-guide-to-healthy-feet-
and-ankles-simple-steps-to-prevent-injury-and-run-stronger-1st-
edition-dr-brian-w-fullem/
textbookfull.com
ENGINEERING
MATHEMATICS
with MATLAB®
ENGINEERING
MATHEMATICS
with MATLAB®
Won Y. Yang
Young K. Choi
Jaekwon Kim
Man Cheol Kim
H. Jin Kim
Taeho Im
CRC Press
Taylor & Francis Group
6000 Broken Sound Parkway NW, Suite 300
Boca Raton, FL 33487-2742
This book contains information obtained from authentic and highly regarded sources. Reasonable efforts have been made to publish reliable data and
information, but the author and publisher cannot assume responsibility for the validity of all materials or the consequences of their use. The authors and
publishers have attempted to trace the copyright holders of all material reproduced in this publication and apologize to copyright holders if permission
to publish in this form has not been obtained. If any copyright material has not been acknowledged please write and let us know so we may rectify in any
future reprint.
Except as permitted under U.S. Copyright Law, no part of this book may be reprinted, reproduced, transmitted, or utilized in any form by any electronic,
mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying, microfilming, and recording, or in any information storage or
retrieval system, without written permission from the publishers.
For permission to photocopy or use material electronically from this work, please access www.copyright.com (http://www.copyright.com/) or contact
the Copyright Clearance Center, Inc. (CCC), 222 Rosewood Drive, Danvers, MA 01923, 978-750-8400. CCC is a not-for-profit organization that provides
licenses and registration for a variety of users. For organizations that have been granted a photocopy license by the CCC, a separate system of payment
has been arranged.
Trademark Notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or registered trademarks, and are used only for identification and explanation
without intent to infringe.
Visit the Taylor & Francis Web site at
http://www.taylorandfrancis.com
and the CRC Press Web site at
http://www.crcpress.com
To our parents and families
who love and support us
and
to our teachers and students
who enriched our knowledge
vii
Contents
PREFACE XIII
Chapter 1: Vectors and Matrices .................................................................................................... 1
1.1 Vectors ..................................................................................................................................... 1
1.1.1 Geometry with Vector .................................................................................................. 1
1.1.2 Dot Product .................................................................................................................. 2
1.1.3 Cross Product ............................................................................................................... 6
1.1.4 Lines and Planes ........................................................................................................... 9
1.1.5 Vector Space .............................................................................................................. 17
1.1.6 Coordinate Systems .................................................................................................... 18
1.1.7 Gram–Schmidt Orthonolization ................................................................................. 29
1.2 Matrices ................................................................................................................................. 32
1.2.1 Matrix Algebra ........................................................................................................... 32
1.2.2 Rank and Row/Column Spaces .................................................................................. 32
1.2.3 Determinant and Trace ............................................................................................... 34
1.2.4 Eigenvalues and Eigenvectors .................................................................................... 35
1.2.5 Inverse of a Matrix ..................................................................................................... 39
1.2.6 Similarity Transformation and Diagonalization ......................................................... 42
1.2.7 Special Matrices ......................................................................................................... 44
1.2.8 Positive Definiteness .................................................................................................. 47
1.2.9 Matrix Inversion Lemma ............................................................................................ 48
1.2.10 LU, Cholesky, QR, and Singular Value Decompositions ........................................... 49
1.2.11 Geometrical Meaning of Eigenvalues/Eigenvectors ................................................... 50
1.3 Systems of Linear Equations ............................................................................................... 55
1.3.1 Nonsingular Case ....................................................................................................... 55
1.3.2 Undetermined Case — Minimum-Norm Solution.................................................... 56
1.3.3 Overdetermined Case — Least-Squares Error Solution ........................................... 58
1.3.4 Gauss(ian) Elimination ............................................................................................... 61
1.3.5 RLS (Recursive Least Squares) Algorithm ................................................................ 65
Problems ....................................................................................................................................... 69
Chapter 2: Vector Calculus ............................................................................................................ 99
2.1 Derivatives............................................................................................................................. 99
2.2 Vector Functions................................................................................................................. 104
2.3 Velocity and Acceleration .................................................................................................. 107
2.4 Divergence and Curl........................................................................................................... 113
2.5 Line Integrals and Path Independence ............................................................................. 127
2.5.1 Line Integrals ............................................................................................................ 127
2.5.2 Path Independence .................................................................................................... 132
2.6 Double Integrals ................................................................................................................. 134
2.7 Green's Theorem ................................................................................................................ 138
2.8 Surface Integrals................................................................................................................. 142
2.9 Stokes' Theorem ................................................................................................................. 149
viii Contents
References …………………………………………………………………………………………726
Index ………………………………………………………………………………………………727
xiii
Preface
This book has been authored to help the students studying basic mathematical stuff that can be met
up with in the course of engineering under the name of ‘engineering mathematics’. They are
supposed to have taken at least two freshman-level courses, one on differentiation/integration and
one on linear algebra (vector and matrix). One more course on the basic level of MATLAB is
recommended.
It is not the aim of this book to provide any foundation in the mathematical theory since the
authors are not so knowledgeable as to do it. The first aim of this book is to help the readers
understand the concepts, techniques, terminologies, and equations appearing in the existing books
on engineering mathematics while using MATLAB software for computation that would be time-
consuming, tedious, and error-prone with no computing device. Needless to say, the readers are
recommended to learn some basic usage of MATLAB software that is available from the MATLAB
help manual or the on-line documents at the website <http://www.mathworks.com/>. However,
they are not required to be so good at MATLAB since most programs in this book have been
composed carefully and completely so that they can be understood in connection with
related/referred equations and algorithms. The readers are expected to get used to the MATLAB
software while trying to modify/use the MATLAB codes in this book for solving the end-of-chapter
problems or their own problems. The second and main aim of this book is to make even a novice at
both MATLAB and mathematics become acquainted, at least comfortable, with MATLAB as well
as mathematics while running the MATLAB codes on his/her computer, trying to understand what
is going on among the equations, and making an interpretation of derived results or formulas. Is it
too much to expect that a novice will become interested in engineering mathematics and
simultaneously, fall in love with MATLAB, which is a universal language for engineers and
scientists, after having read this book through? Is it just the authors’ imagination that the readers
would think of this book describing and explaining many concepts in MATLAB rather than in
English? In any case, the authors have no intention to hide their hope that this book will be one of
the all-the-time-reserved books in most libraries and can be found always on the desks of most
engineers who are interested in developing their insight and getting an overview rather than
repeating impractical computations when studying engineering mathematics. The features of this
book can be summarized as follows:
1. This book presents more MATLAB programs for studying engineering mathematics than any
existent books with the same or similar titles as an approach to explain most things using
MATLAB and figures rather than English and equations.
2. Most MATLAB programs are presented in a complete form so that the readers can run them
instantly with no programming skill and focus on understanding the mathematical
manipulation process and making interpretations of the results obtained by running the
programs.
3. The solutions for most examples are plotted for visualization using the related MATLAB
programs because graphs are not only easier to understand than numeric values or literal
expressions but also helpful in grasping the concept.
xiv Preface
4. Authors never think that this book can replace the existent books made by the great authors.
They neither expect that this book can take the place of the MATLAB manual. Instead, this
book aims to bridge the gap between MATLAB software and theory, equations appearing in
the field of engineering mathematics so that the readers can feel free to utilize the MATLAB
software for studying mathematical stuff and become much more interested in engineering
mathematics than before reading this book.
The contents of this book are derived from the works of many (known or unknown) great
scientists, scholars, and researchers, all of whom are deeply appreciated. We would like to thank the
reviewers for their valuable comments and suggestions, which contribute to enriching this book.
We also thank the people of the School of Electronic & Electrical Engineering, Chung-Ang
University for giving us an academic environment. Without affections and supports of our families
and friends, this book could not be written. Special thanks should be given to the graduate students,
Seungjoon Lee, Changhyeon Kim, and Wonchul Kim at the department of Aerospace Engineering
in Seoul National University for their invaluable help in correction. We gratefully acknowledge the
editorial and production staff (including Ms. Aastha Sharma and Ms. Michele Dimont) of CRC
Press (Taylor & Francis Group) for their kind, efficient, and encouraging guidance.
Program files can be downloaded from <http://wyyang53.com.ne.kr/>. Any questions, comments,
and suggestions regarding this book are welcome and they should be mailed to
wyyang53@hanmail.net.
1.1 VECTORS
1 0 0
u x 0 , u y 1 , u z 0 (1.1.2)
0 0 1
1
2 Chapter 1 Vectors and Matrices
2 1 3
az a 1 , b 1 , c 2
uz 2 0 2
ayuy
ux ax
(a) Different plots of the same vector [2 1 1]T (b) The sum of two vectors by the parallelogram law
Figure 1.1 Direction (slope) field for a first-order differential equation
Figure 1.1 Plots of a vector and the sum of two vectors
Force, velocity, and acceleration are examples of vector quantities. Note that the vectors are most
often written in a column vector rather than in a row vector.
Fig. 1.1(a) shows the three unit vectors u x, u y, u z (each along the +x-, +y-, and +z-axes that are
orthogonal) and different parallel arrows (with the same length and direction), which denote an
identical vector [2 1 1]T wherever they may start and end. Fig. 1.1(b) shows the parallelogram law
for vector addition, that the sum of two vectors is represented by the diagonal of the parallelogram
having the two arrows representing the two vectors (with an identical starting point) as sides.
u x u x u x u y u x u z 1 0 0
T T T
ux
T T
u x u y u z u x u y u z uTy u u u u Tu u Tu u Tu 0 1 0 (1.1.4a)
x y z y x y y y z
u z u z u x u z u y u z u z 0 0 1
T T T T
(1.1.3)
ux ux ||ux ||||u x || cos 0o 1, u y u y 1, u z uz 1
(1.1.4b)
o
ux u y u y u x ||ux || ||u y || cos90 0, u y u z u z u y 0, u z u x u x u z 0
(Proof)
(1.1.4)
a b ( a x u x ay u y a z u z ) (bx u x by u y bz u z ) a x bx ay by a z bz
Note that the magnitude, called the (Euclidean) norm or l 2 -norm, of a vector a can be found from
the dot product of a and itself as
|| a || ||a||2 a a a x2 a 2y a z2 (1.1.5)
Note also that two vectors are orthogonal or perpendicular if and only if their dot product is zero:
a b || a |||| b|| cos ab 0 ab denoted by a b (1.1.6)
2
1.1 Vectors 3
(1.1.3) a b (1.1.3) ax bx ay by a z bz ax bx a y by az bz
cos ab ab cos 1 (1.1.7)
||a||||b|| ||a||||b|| ||a||||b||
b
c ab a
a || c || 2 || a || 2 || b || 2 2|| a|||| b|| cos ab
projb a
ab ab b
b
projba
Figure 1.2 Dot product and the law of cosines Figure 1.3 Projections of a on b
(1.1.3) a b b
comp ba || a ||cos ab a (1.1.9)
||b|| ||b||
We can multiply this with the unit vector in the direction of b, i.e., b/||b|| to find the projection of a
on b as
b (1.1.9) b b b
proj ba (comp ba) a a b (1.1.10)
||b|| ||b|| ||b|| ||b||2
b
proj b a a proj ba a a b
(1.1.10)
(1.1.11)
||b||2
where b is the vector of magnitude ||b|| and direction perpendicular to b (see Fig. 1.3).
4 Chapter 1 Vectors and Matrices
1.5
0.5
0
-1 0 X 2 -2
n 1 x0 x1 a
(1.1.9) (1.1.13)
|| p 21|| |compn p 01 | p 01 y0 y1 b
||n|| a 2 b2 c2 z0 z1 c
(1.1.10)
a
n (1.1.15) ax1 by1 cz1 d ax by cz d a
1
p 21 projn p 01 (compn p01 ) b 1 2 12 12 b
||n|| a 2 b 2 c 2 c
a 2 b2 c2 a b c c
(1.1.16)
The projection p2 of the point p1 onto the plane can be found by adding p21 to p1 as
(1.1.16)
x1 ax by cz d a
p 2 p1 p 21 y1 1 2 12 12 b (1.1.17)
z1 a b c c
1.1 Vectors 5
%em01f04.m
clear, clf % clear the workspace memory, clear the current figure window
x=[-2:0.1:2]; y=[-2:0.1:2]; [X,Y]=meshgrid(x,y); % x- and y-grids
a=1; b=-1; c=9; d=2; Z=(-d-a*X-b*Y)/c; % Plane equation (1.1.12)
n=[a b c].'; % Normal vector to the plane
mesh(X,Y,Z), hold on
p1=[-0.5 0.5 2].'; % A point as a column vector
% An arbitrary point on the plane
p0=zeros(3,1); p0(1)=p1(1)+1; p0(2)=p1(2)-1;
p0(3)=(-d-a*p0(1)-b*p0(2))/c; % fix p0 on the plane satisfying Eq.(1.1.12)
p01=p0-p1; % The vector from p1 to p0
un=n/norm(n); % The unit normal vector
p21=dot(p01,un)*un % Eq.(1.1.15): Projection of p01 on n
plot3(p0(1),p0(2),p0(3),'o'), plot3(p1(1),p1(2),p1(3),'rx') %Points p0, p1
quiver3(p0(1),p0(2),p0(3),un(1),un(2),un(3),0) % un from p0
quiver3(p1(1),p1(2),p1(3),p01(1),p01(2),p01(3),0) % p01 from p0
quiver3(p1(1),p1(2),p1(3),p21(1),p21(2),p21(3),0) % p21 from p1
p2=p1+p21; % Projection point p2 of p1 onto the plane: Eq.(1.1.17)
plot3(p2(1),p2(2),p2(3),'bv'), axis('equal'), grid on
xlabel('x'), ylabel('y'), zlabel('z'), view(12,15), shg
Fig. 1.4 has been plotted by running the above MATLAB script “em01f04.m” with a point
p1 [ 0.5 0.5 2]T and a plane equation x y 9 z 2 0 , which uses the MATLAB function
‘dot()’ to compute the dot product. Note that the MATLAB function ‘quiver3()’ (with scale
factor set to 1 for no scaling) has been used to draw 3D vectors. See Appendix E.10.
where the equality holds if and only if the two vectors a and b are parallel, i.e., a=k b (k: a scalar).
; || c || || a b || || a || || b || (1.1.19)
a c a b
|| c|| || a b || || a || || b ||
b
Figure 1.5 Triangle inequality
Visit https://textbookfull.com
now to explore a rich
collection of eBooks, textbook
and enjoy exciting offers!
6 Chapter 1 Vectors and Matrices
ab ab
b
b
un
a
a
b a a b
(a) ( b)
The cross (vector, or outer) product of two vectors a=a x u x +a y u y +a z u z and b=b x u x +b y u y +b z u z is
defined as
a b || a |||| b || sin ab u n ( a y bz a z by ) u x ( a z bx a x bz )u y ( a x by a y bx )u z
ux u y u z ay bz az by
ax ay az az bx ax bz (1.1.20)
bx by bz ax by ay bx
where |C| is the determinant (Section 1.2.3) of matrix C and un is the unit normal vector to the plane
spanned by a and b. (A space is said to be spanned by a set of vectors if any vector in the space can
be expressed by a linear combination of the vectors belonging to the set.) Note that the direction of
a×b is given by the right-hand rule in the sense that the thumb points in the direction of a×b if the
forefinger (index finger) and middle finger point in the direction of a and b, respectively, as shown
in Fig. 1.6.
The second equality of Eq. (1.1.20) can be proved by verifying that both sides are equal in terms
of the magnitude and direction (perpendicular to both a and b):
|| a|| 2 || b|| 2 sin 2ab ||u n|| 2 || a||2 || b ||2 (1 cos 2 ab ) || a||2 || b||2 (|| a |||| b ||cosab ) 2
(1.1.3) 2
(a
(1.1.5) x
a 2y az2 )(bx2 by2 bz2 ) (ax bx ay by az bz )2
ax ax bx ax ay bz az by
a (a b ) a y a y by a y az bx ax bz
a by ay b
a z a z bz a z x x
Alternatively, we can use the relations among the unit vectors u x , u y , and u z :
(1.1.20), /2
ux uy uz (1.1.23a), u y u x uz (1.1.24a)
u y uz ux (1.1.23b), u z u y u x (1.1.24b)
uz u x uy (1.1.23c), u x u z u y (1.1.24c)
(1.1.20), 0
u x u x u y u y uz uz 0 (1.1.25)
a b ( a x u x a y u y a z u z ) (bx u x by u y bz u z )
(1.1.23,24,25)
( a y bz a z by ) u x ( a z bx a x bz )u y ( a x by a y bx )u z
( a b) c (b c ) a (c a) b (1.1.26)
as follows:
( a b) c
(1.1.20)
( c x u x c y u y cz u z ) ( a y bz az by )u x ( azbx ax bz )u y ( ax by ay bx )u z
(1.1.3)
c x ( a y bz a z by ) cy ( az bx ax bz ) cz ( axb y ay bx ) (1.1.27b)
(b c ) a
(1.1.20)
( a x u x a y u y a z u z ) (by cz bz c y )u x (bz cx bx cz )u y (bx cy b y cx )u z
(1.1.3)
a x ( by c z b z c y ) a y ( b z c x bx c z ) a z ( b x c y b y c x ) (1.1.27a)
(b c ) a
(1.1.20)
( a x u x a y u y a z u z ) (by cz bz c y )u x (bz cx bx cz )u y (bx cy b y cx )u z
(1.1.3)
bx (c y az c z ay ) by ( cz ax c x az ) bz ( cx ay cy ax ) (1.1.27c)
a (b c ) (c a) b (b a)c (1.1.28)
as follows:
ab
b b
Aprlm || a b || 1
Atrgl ||a b ||
|| a||||b|| sinab 2 c
|| b|| sin ab
|compa×bc |
b
ab ab
a a a
(a) Parallelogram (b) Triangle (c) Parallelepiped
The area of a parallelogram with its sides denoted by two nonparallel vectors a and b can be
computed from the magnitude of the cross product of a and b (see Fig. 1.7(a)):
The area of a triangle with its sides denoted by two nonparallel vectors a and b can also be
computed from the magnitude of the cross product of a and b (see Fig. 1.7(b)):
1 1
A trgl || a b || || a |||| b || sin ab (1.1.32)
2 2
The volume of a parallelepiped with its sides denoted by three nonparallel vectors a, b, and c can be
computed from the magnitude of the triple scalar product or box product of a, b, and c:
a b (1.1.9)
| (a b) c | | c (a b)| || a b || c || a b || | compa×bc |
|| a b|| (1.1.33)
(base parallelogram area) (height)
Why is compa×bc the height of the parallelepiped? Because it is the magnitude of the component of
c along the normal vector a×b to the base plane spanned by a and b (see Fig. 1.7(c)).
The vector equation for the line with direction vector d passing through a point p1 is
p p1 d t with direction vector d (1.1.35)
Accordingly, the vector equation for the line through any two distinct points p1 and p2 is
x x1 d x t , y y1 d y t , z z1 d z t (1.1.37a)
%em01f08.m
p1=[-1 -1 1.5].'; p2=[1 0 2].'; % Two points
plot3(p1(1),p1(2),p1(3),'o', p2(1),p2(2),p2(3),'o'), hold on
d=p2-p1; % Direction vector
t=[-1 2]; % Parametric vector
p=repmat(p1,1,length(t))+(p2-p1)*t; % Vector equation Eq.(1.1.36)
plot3(p(1,:),p(2,:),p(3,:),'r') % Plot the line in a 3D space
O=zeros(3,1); arrow3(p1,O), arrow3(p2,O) % Arrows of p1 and p2 from Origin
view(12,15), grid on
10 Chapter 1 Vectors and Matrices
The vector and Cartesian equations of a plane with normal vector n=[a b c]T passing through a
point p1 =[x1 y1 z 1 ]T (Fig. 1.9(a)) are
n ( p p1 ) 0 (1.1.39a)
and
a ( x x1 ) b ( y y1 ) c ( z z 1 ) 0 (1.1.39b)
This implies that a line from p1 to any point p=[x y z]T on the plane is perpendicular to the normal
vector n.
How do we write the equation for a plane containing some three points p1, p2, and p 3 (Fig.
1.9(b))? It can be obtained from Eq. (1.1.39a) with the normal vector n constructed by the cross
product of the two vectors (p 2 -p 1 ) and (p 3 -p 1 ) on the plane:
0.5d
n 0.5d (E1.1.3)
4.5d
Note that the two vectors obtained as Eqs. (E1.1.1) and (E1.1.3) are virtually equal (with possibly
different lengths and opposite directions) as normal vectors to the plane since they are parallel.
Random documents with unrelated
content Scribd suggests to you:
In the temple of Damia and Auxesia on (i) pottery,
Aegina it became the practice (νόμος) after
the war “to introduce into the temple neither anything else Attic nor
pottery, but to drink there henceforth only out of native jars[857].”
Herodotus mentions this embargo on Attic pottery only as applied to
the one temple on Aegina[858]. But he states that it was observed by
Argives as well as by Aeginetans, which points to the possibility that
the practice prevailed in Argos as well as Aegina. Macan goes as far
as to suggest that it is an “understatement and pseudo-explanation of
a measure or custom for the protection of native ware from Attic
competition[859].” The other measures recorded in this connexion, the
changes in Attic dress and in Peloponnesian brooches, support
Macan’s suggestion. But in the matter of dating he follows earlier
writers who, using very inadequate material, came to conclusions
which can now be shown to be improbable. They date this embargo
in the middle of the sixth century. But in Aegina at any rate Attic
pottery continued to be imported throughout the second half of the
sixth century, while in Argos, where the evidence is less decisive and
abundant, there is no sign of a cessation of Attic imports about 550
B.C. On the other hand both in Argos and Aegina there does appear
to be an abrupt cessation of Attic imports early in the seventh
century. As, further, the general history of Greek pottery shows that
an Argive-Aeginetan embargo on Attic pottery would have had a
strong commercial motive early in the seventh century and none in
the middle of the sixth, there is a strong presumption that the date of
the embargo was not the middle of the sixth century but somewhere
about the beginning of the seventh. To examine the archaeological
evidence here in detail would take us too far from our main enquiry.
It will be found presented in full in an appendix[860].
The war was a great disaster for Athenian (ii) sea-power
naval power. Now the period of greatest and ships,
eclipse for Athens from this point of view was the seventh century.
Throughout it there is no indication whatever of naval activity at
Athens, except a possible war against Mitylene. Even that must be
put at the earliest close on the year 600 B.C., and is to be regarded as
announcing the beginning of the new epoch of activity in the sixth
century[861]; and against it must be set the failure in the struggle with
Megara for Salamis[862]. This had not been the naval position of
Athens earlier. During the dark ages she appears to have been a
considerable naval power. A tradition preserved by Plutarch makes
Athens succeed Crete in the command of the sea[863]: naval power is
implied in Theseus’ expedition to Crete; a poem of Bacchylides[864],
which is illustrated by a vase painting of Euphronios[865], tells how
Theseus went to the depths of the sea to fetch up the ring of Minos,
and the story has been brought by S. Reinach into connexion with
rings such as those of Polycrates and the doges of Venice, and
explained as symbolizing the winning by Theseus of the sea which
had been previously the bride of Minos[866].
The date of these events must not be pressed. The period of this
sea-power is plainly the dark age that followed the breaking up of the
Cretan and Mycenaean civilization. It is the period of the pottery
known as Geometric, and the Athenian Geometric, the Dipylon ware,
again and again shows pictures of ships. Thirty-nine examples are
quoted by Torr[867], enough, as pointed out by Helbig[868], to prove the
important rôle played by the Athenian navy in the life of Athens of
that age. The Dipylon ships, as remarked twenty years ago by
Helbig[869], show that already in the eighth century Athens was
preparing to found her power on her navy. It requires some such
catastrophic explanation as has just been offered to account for her
complete set back in the seventh.
One result in Athens of the reverse in (iii) dress.
Aegina, so Herodotus declares, was a
revolution in the dress of the Athenian women, who gave up the
Doric costume, which was made of wool and fastened with pins, and
adopted in its place the Ionic, which consisted of sewn garments
made of linen. The passage is a locus classicus among writers on
Greek dress, and it must be at once admitted that nearly all of them
accept a date late in the first half of the sixth century[870]. So late a
date seems to me to be untenable. It can be reconciled neither with
the statements of Thucydides on the subject of Athenian dress[871],
nor with the evidence of extant monuments[872]. The sumptuary laws
on women’s dress passed by Solon in 594 B.C.[873] were plainly
directed against the Ionian costume. They show that it must have
reached Athens by about 600 B.C. and offer no evidence that it had
not done so considerably earlier. Bury dates the introduction of
Ionian dress into Athens “c. 650 (?)[874].”
Among the Aeginetans and Argives as a After the war the
result of their victory over Athens a change Argives and
was introduced in what Herodotus calls the Aeginetans make
their brooches
“measure” (μέτρον) of Aeginetan and Argive “half as big
brooches (περόναι). Herodotus states that again.”
this change affected both the dedications at
the temple of Damia and Auxesia[875], and also the general
manufacture and use. The way he tells the story explains why he goes
beyond the temple when speaking of the pins, but does not do so in
the case of the pottery. The exclusion of Attic pottery from the
Aeginetan temple, or rather the exclusive use for temple purposes of
local ware, was in Herodotus’ days a ritualistic survival. The large
brooches on the other hand had continued in general use. “Now the
women of Argos and Aegina even to my own days wore brooches of
increased size.” Very possibly Herodotus had himself noticed them.
It is the account of this change in the “measure” of the Aeginetan and
Argive brooches that confirms the connexion of Pheidon with the
origin of the Aeginetan coinage.
The new practice was in Herodotus’ own words: “to make the
brooches half as big again as the then established measure.” It is
probably significant that, both before and after the change, the
brooches have a standard “measure.” The tendency of articles of
jewellery in early periods to be of a fixed weight is a familiar one.
Numerous instances are quoted in Ridgeway’s Origin of Metallic
Currency[876]. Not only so, but these fixed weights are repeatedly
found corresponding with or anticipating the coin standards of the
places they belong to.
It may be objected that the word μέτρον does not mean weight.
This is so when it is contrasted with σταθμός[877]; but it appears to
have been used also in a more comprehensive sense[878]. The
Athenian μετρονόμοι[879] must have inspected weights as well as
measures. μέτρον is presumably applied to both, and to a fifth
century Greek there would be no question of its referring to anything
but weight when applied to jewellery[880].
The change introduced by the Argives and The Aeginetan
Aeginetans after driving the Athenians from drachma was
Aegina was to make the “measure” of their half as big again
as the Attic.
brooches half as big again as what it had
previously been. Now this is approximately the relationship in weight
of the earliest Aeginetan drachmae to the earliest drachmae struck
on the Euboeic standard. Later, in Herodotus’ own times, the relative
weights were four to three. But the earliest Aeginetan drachmae
weighed a little more than those of later issues[881]. On the other
hand, as stated by Percy Gardner[882] in discussing Solon’s
“augmentation” of the Athenian coins, the earliest Attic or rather
Euboeic drachma[883] weighed less than those of post-Solonian times.
The weight of the Aeginetan drachma as determined from the early
didrachms quoted above (p. 171, n. 6) is just over six grammes, as
compared with the 5·85 grammes of later issues, while that of the
earliest Attic Euboeic drachma as determined from the coins of p.
171, n. 8 is just over four grammes, as compared with the 4·26
grammes of later issues[884].
Thus the original Aeginetan drachma seems to have been just half
as heavy again as the earliest Attic[885]. This ratio is accepted by
Ridgeway[886], who regards it as invented to make ten silver pieces
worth one gold when gold was fifteen times as precious as silver,
while later, when silver rose to be worth 3/40 of its weight in gold,
the silver pieces were slightly diminished in weight, in order that ten
of them might still be the equivalent of one of gold[887].
Let us now return to the one passage of Summary of the
Herodotus, in which he refers by name to evidence of
the Argive tyrant. Herodotus.
In that passage he speaks of Pheidon as “the man who made their
measures for the Peloponnesians[888].” The force of the definite
article that precedes the Greek μέτρα has not always been sufficiently
stressed. More than one recent writer begins his discussion of the
passage by translating τὰ μέτρα “a system of measures.” The
subsequent argument has naturally suffered. τὰ μέτρα can be no
other measures than those associated with the Peloponnesus in
Herodotus’ own days, namely those of the famous Aeginetan
standard, employed in particular for the coinage of the island[889].
Other scholars have regarded the statement that Pheidon struck the
first coins in Aegina as merely an amplification by later writers of
these very words. They argue that “the measures” plainly meant the
Aeginetan standard, and so suggested the famous Aeginetan coinage.
This latter view assumes of course that the amplifications of Ephorus
are not to be found in Herodotus himself. But what are the facts? The
establishment of Aeginetan measures in the Peloponnesus are
alluded to by Herodotus not only in the passage about the Argive
tyrant in Book VI but also very possibly in the passage in Book V that
describes the early Argive expedition to Aegina. In this latter passage
the measures are said to have been the result of the expedition. Both
expedition and tyrant are probably to be dated early in the seventh
century. That is also the date to which numismatists generally assign
the first drachmae struck in Aegina, struck too on a standard that,
like that of our brooches, was half again as great as that previously in
use.
It is hard to avoid the inference that when the fourth century
writers say that Pheidon coined in Aegina, they are faithfully
reporting a genuine tradition.
It has indeed been maintained that the Sceptical views
whole Herodotean account of the early on these
relations of Argos, Aegina, and Athens is chapters of
Herodotus stated
unhistorical[890]. The arguments brought and answered.
forward to support this destructive view
are: (i) that the episode is timeless and its timelessness must be due
to its unhistorical character, (ii) that it must be unhistorical because
it cannot, as alleged by Herodotus, have been the cause of the war of
487 B.C., which must have been due to the natural rivalry of the two
neighbouring states. As regards the first of these two arguments, the
preceding pages have, it is hoped, shown that the episode is not
timeless: as regards the second, it is enough to point out that it
assumes that war cannot breed war, that no war can be due to two
causes, and that an incident cannot be historical if it is alleged as
leading to results that it cannot have in fact produced. The fact that
arguments such as these were accepted for publication in a periodical
of high repute less than a generation back shows how much the
whole world of scholarship was infected by the spirit of uncritical
scepticism that has left its mark in some quarters on that of the
present age.
Others again like Wilamowitz[891] regard the narrative of
Herodotus V. 82–88 as simply a reflexion backwards of the state of
affairs existing in 487 B.C.[892], when Athens attacked Aegina, and the
Aeginetans “called to their aid the same people as before, the
Argives[893].” They argue that (i) the story is our only evidence for
hatred between Athens and Aegina much before 506 B.C., (ii) the
Argive-Aeginetan brooches as compared with the broochless
Athenian costume[894], the embargo on Attic pottery at the Aeginetan
temple, and the posture of the kneeling statues (pleading before the
Athenian invaders) may all have been referred in Herodotus’ days to
the existing hatred and recent wars between Athens and Aegina, (iii)
Herodotus puts back the Athenian disaster into the timeless period
because the miracle and the change of costume required an early
date, and the story does not fit the war of 487 B.C., since the famous
Sophanes[895], who fought in it, lived till 464. Herodotus, they say,
gives no account of a disaster to the Athenian fleet in 487 because he
had used it up for this early reflexion.
Of these points (i) is answered by the whole of this chapter, (ii) and
(iii) fall with (i), besides which (ii) contains many improbabilities,
e.g. that the pottery in an Aeginetan temple should without historic
reason have suggested to any fifth century Greek an early war with
Athens, while (iii) assumes an Athenian disaster in 487 B.C., whereas
Thucydides declares that Athens was successful in that war[896].
There is nothing suspicious in the Aeginetans having twice in two
hundred years attained some sort of thalassocracy, and having on
both occasions come as a result into collision with Athens. It is
perfectly natural for the Aeginetans on a second occasion to appeal to
allies who had previously helped them so effectively and with such
profit to themselves. Macan[897] observes that the Herodotean
account of the feud between Athens and Aegina is remarkably
uninfluenced by contemporary politics and interests. He suggests[898]
dating the subjection of Aegina to Epidaurus to the reign of Pheidon,
and the revolt of the island from Epidaurus to the time of Pheidon’s
fall. But why in that case does the account speak of a revolt from
Epidaurus, if it was really a revolt from the famous Argive tyranny?
The whole narrative finds a more appropriate setting if regarded as
one chapter in the history of Pheidon himself.
Only, why in this case is the name of Why Pheidon is
Pheidon nowhere mentioned? It is one not mentioned in
thing to omit details in a biography four them.
lines in length. It is quite another to omit so prominent a name in a
narrative that runs to seven whole chapters. But the omission,
though at first sight surprising, is capable of explanation. The
Herodotean story appears to have been derived from the temple of
Damia and Auxesia[899]. It was told Herodotus not in connexion with
any royal monument, but to explain certain offerings of pottery and
jewellery that he saw in the temple. Not a single personal name
occurs in the whole narrative, and there is no particular reason why
there should. There may actually have been motives for not
introducing them. The account of the events given to Herodotus in
the Aeginetan temple of Damia and Auxesia would naturally not
emphasize the part played by the Argive tyrant. The Athenian
version, to which also Herodotus alludes, would have still better
reason for trying to forget the name of Pheidon. If my whole
interpretation of these events is not entirely wrong, Pheidon dealt
the Athenians what was probably the most crushing blow they had
ever received down to the days when Herodotus wrote his history.
The personal name may be omitted from the same motive that made
the Athenians speak of the Aeginetan drachma as the “fat” drachma,
which they are said to have done, “refusing to call it Aeginetan out of
hatred of the Aeginetans[900].” Sparta again had taken sides against
Pheidon at Olympia[901], and would have had no interest in
perpetuating the name of the man who had almost barred their way
to the hegemony of the Peloponnese.
Ephorus’ account of Pheidon’s conquests and inventions is derived
neither from Attic nor from Aeginetan sources. As seen already[902]
the source of his statement about Pheidon coining in Aegina was
most probably the Argive Heraeum. Herodotus claims to use Argive
sources, but for him the war is primarily a matter between the
Athenians and the Aeginetans, whose subsequent hatred of one
another it is intended to explain. Thus we appear to have three rival
or even hostile traditions confirming one another, so that the variety
of sources adds in a real way to the credibility of the resultant
narrative.
The notices about the coinage are not the Pheidon and
only evidence for associating Pheidon with Aegina, further
Aegina. According to Ephorus “he evidence from
Ephorus:
completely recovered the lot of Temenos, Pheidon
which had previously been split into several recovered the lot
parts[903].” Temenos appears in the of Temenos,
genealogies as great great grandson of which included
Heracles, and founder of the Dorian Aegina.
dynasty at Argos[904]. He and his sons and his son-in-law between
them are represented as securing the greater part of the North-east
Peloponnese. Aegina fell to his son-in-law Deiophontes, who went to
the island from Epidaurus[905].
The operations described in Herodotus V. 82–88, by which the
Argives crossed from Epidaurus and drove the Athenians out of
Aegina and put an end to the Epidaurians being tributary to
Athens[906], are almost beyond doubt to be identified with the
recovery by Argos of the portion of the lot of Temenos that had been
secured by Deiophontes.
It is true that this account of the recovery Traces of this
of the lot of Temenos is first certainly met recovery in other
with in Strabo, whose authority is only the passages of
Herodotus.
fourth century Ephorus. But there are hints
that Ephorus is here to be trusted. There is the evidence of
Herodotus that from an unspecified earlier date down to about 550
B.C. the Argives had possessed the whole east coast of the
Peloponnesus and “the island of Cythera and the rest of the
islands[907].” The most likely period for Argos to have acquired this
territory is the reign of Pheidon. Pheidon according to Strabo[908]
“had deprived the Spartans of the hegemony of the Peloponnese,”
and it is the Spartans who shortly before Croesus asked for their
help, had wrested from the Argives “Cythera and the rest of the
islands.” About 668 B.C., i.e. probably in Pheidon’s reign, the Argives
had beaten the Spartans in the battle of Hysiae, which decided the
possession of the strip of coast land south of the Argolid[909].
Aegina is not mentioned in these proceedings, but C. Mueller may
be right in including it among “the rest of the islands[910].” The Hysiae
campaign is roughly contemporary with the second Messenian war,
in which Argos took part against the Spartans[911], and of which
indeed it may have been an incident. Now in that war the Samians
took part by sea against the Argives[912], and it is natural to connect
this action of theirs with their repeated attacks on Aegina in the days
of the Samian King Amphikrates, at some period indefinitely before
the reign of Polycrates. The Samians were certainly a naval power in
the first half of the seventh century. The four triremes built for them
in 704 B.C. marked for Thucydides an epoch in naval history[913].
About 668 B.C. Kolaios the Samian made his famous voyage beyond
the Straits of Gibraltar to the Spanish seaport of Tartessus, a voyage
that implies much previous naval enterprise on the Samians’ part.
The rivalry with Aegina was probably commercial. Kolaios and his
crew returned from the “silver rooted streams” of the Tartessus
river[914], having “made the greatest profits from cargoes of all Greeks
of whom we have accurate information, excepting Sostratos the
Aeginetan: for it is impossible for anyone else to rival him[915].”
Samian attacks on Aegina are thus particularly likely to have
happened about the time of the second Messenian war.
A century ago C. Mueller[916] argued that some event or other
connecting Samos with Aegina must have been closely connected
with the revolt of Aegina from Epidaurus, since the revolt was
described in the History of Samos of the Samian historian Duris
(born about 340 B.C.)[917]. From this he proceeds to advocate a date
for the revolt not very long before the war between Samos and
Aegina of 520 B.C. Arguments based on the laws of digression
observed by a writer whose works are known to us only in a few
fragments need to be used with caution. If Duris is any indication
whatever for the date of the revolt, he leaves an open choice between
the time of the war of 520 B.C. and that of the days of King
Amphikrates; and as between these two the evidence shows that the
earlier is probable while the latter is almost impossible.
As independent evidence these hints would be of scarcely any
value. As confirmation of a definite but disputable statement their
value is considerable.
The recovery of ancestral domains is a Summary of
favourite euphemism among military Pheidon’s
conquerors for their policy of annexation. activities
according to
The chronology, both relative and absolute,
Strabo (=
of Strabo’s summary of Pheidon’s career Ephorus).
has every appearance of authenticity.
Pheidon first recovers the lot of Temenos, then “invents” his
measures and coinage, and after that attempts to expand eastwards
and southwards to secure the whole inheritance of Heracles, or in
other words aims at the suzerainty of the whole Peloponnese, and to
that end celebrates the Olympian games. This last event is probably
to be dated 668 B.C. The coinage must be put indefinitely earlier in
his reign, a perfectly reasonable date on numismatic and historical
grounds, and the recovery of the lot of Temenos a few years earlier
still.
The date thus reached is confirmed by the histories of the two
other leading cities of this part of the Peloponnese, Sicyon and
Corinth.
Sicyon formed part of the lot of Temenos, Pheidon and
[918]
and was held by his son Phalkes . About other parts of the
670 B.C. the city fell under the tyranny of lot of Temenos:
(i) Sicyon.
the able and powerful family of Orthagoras,
whose policy was marked by extreme hostility to Argos[919]. Pheidon
plainly can have had no footing in Sicyon during the rule of the
Orthagorids. But the unusual stability and popularity of the tyranny
at Sicyon have often been explained, not without reason, as due to its
popular anti-Dorian policy. During the second Messenian war, which
Pausanias dates 686–668 B.C.[920], so that the rise of Orthagoras
coincides with its conclusion, the Sicyonians appear to have acted in
close co-operation with the Argives[921]. The position and policy of the
Sicyonian tyrants becomes particularly comprehensible if they had
risen to power as leaders of a racial uprising that put an end in the
city to a Dorian ascendancy that dated originally from the days of
Temenos[922] and had been revived by Pheidon[923].
Whether Corinth formed part of the lot of (ii) Corinth.
Temenos is uncertain. Probably it did.
Strabo and Ptolemy exclude the city from the Argolid[924]. But on the
other hand Homer speaks of it as being “in a corner of horse rearing
Argos[925],” and Pausanias states that “the district of Corinth is part of
Argolis[926],” and that he believes it to have been so in Homeric
times[927]. The conflicting statements of these excellent authorities
are best reconciled by supposing them to be referring to different
periods. If this is so, and if, as well might be, all the domains of
Homeric Argos passed to its first Dorian lord, then Corinth formed
part of the lot of Temenos. A Temenid Corinth is perhaps implied in
Apollodorus[928], where Temenos, the two sons of Aristodemus, and
Kresphontes “when they had conquered the Peloponnese, set up
three altars of Zeus Patroos and sacrificed on them and drew lots for
the cities. The first lot was Argos, the second Sparta, the third
Messene.”
For connexions between Pheidon and Corinth we have only a story
told by Plutarch and a Scholiast on Apollonius Rhodius[929] of which
the salient points are that (a) Pheidon tries to annex Corinth; (b) the
Bacchiads and Archias are the pro-Argive party; (c) the fall of the
Bacchiads (which led to the rise of the tyrant Cypselus) meant the
overthrow of Argive influence.
So far the story is all of a piece, and supports the view that the
simultaneous establishment of Cypselus in Corinth and Orthagoras
in Sicyon may have been part cause and part result of the fall of
Pheidon and the breaking up again of the lot of Temenos. Such a
suggestion harmonizes well with the friendship that existed between
the Corinthian and Sicyon tyrants[930].
There are however chronological difficulties in this interpretation
of the Pheidon Archias story. In the story (i) the fall of the Bacchiads
is made contemporary with the foundation of Syracuse, i.e. it must
presumably be dated about 734 B.C.[931]; (ii) Pheidon is put some
time before this event, his contemporary Habron being grandfather
of Archias’ favourite Actaeon: the Marmor Parium enters Pheidon
before Archias.
In a highly romantic narrative like that of Archias and Actaeon the
last thing to be looked for is a reliable and exact chronology.
Impossible dates may mean impossible statements; but on the other
hand they may mean merely a confusion of facts of different dates, or
again, the facts may be coherent, and the dates just simply wrong.
In the present case, except for the relative dating of Archias and
Pheidon, the historic background is perfectly coherent, if the events
are put early in the seventh century. To accept the 750 date for
Pheidon sets him right in relation to Archias, but leaves the rest of
the story in the air. There is indeed always the refuge of assuming a
double banishment of the Bacchiads. But the idea of a double
banishment, traces of which might easily be discovered by the
reduplicating school of historians, is deservedly suspect, and may
have arisen from a double dating due to double dating of Pheidon. If
there really were two banishments, the story better suits the second.
Neither Plutarch nor the Scholiast on Apollonius gives any
absolute dates; and those of the Parian Marble, which does, are
impossible. The Marble dates Pheidon 895 B.C. and Archias 758.
Pheidon is also indeed made contemporary with an Athenian who
according to Castor held the office of king from 864 to 846 B.C.[932]
From 846 to 758 is a possible, though improbably long interval
between Pheidon and Archias, if as the story tells us, the latter had as
favourite the grandson of one of Pheidon’s contemporaries; but even
so the dating is so unsatisfactory, that the latest editor of the Parian
Marble[933] has suggested transposing Archias and Pheidon. But,
apart from other difficulties, the resultant early date for Archias is
altogether against the evidence. There is no need to put him back
into the ninth century merely because it is not unlikely that Greeks at
that period were already making their way to Sicily. The antedating
of Pheidon has already been accounted for, and he appears to have
taken back Archias with him part of the way.
The date of Archias is a problem any way. But it is not difficult to
suggest a possible chronology. Pheidon’s fall[934] was probably rapid
(a proof of his hubris). His rise was probably slow. Being a hereditary
monarch, he may well have ruled for fifty years, from about 715 to
665 B.C. It was early in his career that he began to carry out his
designs on Corinth. Archias, who had founded Syracuse in 734, gave
him support. We are told no details, but the alliances of the period of
the second Messenian war and the naval struggle in the Saronic Gulf
must have supplied abundant motives and inducements. Bacchiad
government under Argive protection continued till Pheidon fell,
which meant also the fall of the Bacchiads themselves. They
withdrew to the far west. Demaratus penetrated as far as Tarquinii.
Large numbers doubtless settled at Syracuse. The order of events just
outlined coincides entirely with the extant narratives, except in the
one matter of Syracuse, and there the divergence is very
comprehensible. The founder of Syracuse had supported Pheidon.
Pheidon’s fall had led to a great influx of pro-Argive Corinthians into
Syracuse, and threw Archias back entirely onto his Sicilian colony. If
this is what really happened, it would not be surprising if the fall of
Pheidon came to be regarded as having led to the original foundation
of Syracuse.
The chief doubt however as to the Pheidon of
historical truth of the Argive tyrant’s Corinth: is he
interference in Corinth is caused by certain identical with the
Argive?
references to a Corinthian Pheidon,
described by Aristotle as “one of the earliest lawgivers[935].” When an
Argive Pheidon is reported as making his appearance in Corinthian
history, is it a mistake due to the confusing of two separate
personalities? If two existed, they were unquestionably confused. A
Pindar Scholiast says that “a certain Pheidon, a man of Corinth,
invented measures and weights[936].”
But there is an alternative possibility. The Corinthian Pheidon may
be only one aspect of the Argive: this is suggested by the Pindar
Scholiast later in the same ode, where he says that “the Pheidon who
first struck their measures (κόψας τὸ μέτρον) for the Corinthians
was an Argive[937].” Too much stress must not be laid on such very
confused statements[938]. At best they can only corroborate other and
better evidence. This however is not altogether lacking. When
Karanos, the kinsman of Pheidon, went to Macedonia and occupied
Edessa and the lands of the Argeadae[939], Bacchiads from Corinth
settled near by among the Lynkestai[940].
A lawgiver who was “one of the earliest” can have arisen in Corinth
only before the establishment of the tyranny in 657 B.C. On the other
hand lawgivers seem to have been mainly a seventh century
phenomenon in Greece, and the most natural time for one to have
been appointed in Corinth is when the Bacchiad nobility was losing
its ascendancy, a process which may be imagined as beginning early
in the seventh century or at the end of the eighth. Plutarch describes
Pheidon’s designs on Corinth as formed at the beginning of his
career. Everything points to the Argive tyrant having had a long
reign. There is nothing improbable in the supposition that the rival
factions in Corinth invited to act as their lawgiver a young sovereign
of unusual ability who ruled a city of great traditions but not at the
time particularly powerful[941]. I have already suggested the course
taken by events in Corinth after Pheidon had once secured a position
in the city. One passage remains to be quoted that makes it still more
probable both that the Corinthian lawgiver was the Argive tyrant,
and that events in Corinth took something like the course that I have
suggested. According to Nicholas of Damascus[942] Pheidon out of
friendship went to the help of the Corinthians during a civil war: an
attack was made by his supporters, and he was killed[943]. An intimate
connexion from the beginning of his career with the great trading
and manufacturing city of the Isthmus would go far to explain the
commercial and financial inventiveness that was the distinguishing
feature of this royal tyrant[944].
Chapter VII. Corinth