100% found this document useful (5 votes)
53 views

C++ Programming From Problem Analysis to Program Design 8th Edition Malik Test Bankdownload

The document provides links to various test banks and solutions manuals for C++ programming and other subjects, including editions of 'C++ Programming From Problem Analysis to Program Design' by Malik. It includes a series of true/false and multiple-choice questions related to C++ class concepts, such as member access and class definitions. The questions cover fundamental programming principles and terminology relevant to the C++ language.

Uploaded by

nelyinnys
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
100% found this document useful (5 votes)
53 views

C++ Programming From Problem Analysis to Program Design 8th Edition Malik Test Bankdownload

The document provides links to various test banks and solutions manuals for C++ programming and other subjects, including editions of 'C++ Programming From Problem Analysis to Program Design' by Malik. It includes a series of true/false and multiple-choice questions related to C++ class concepts, such as member access and class definitions. The questions cover fundamental programming principles and terminology relevant to the C++ language.

Uploaded by

nelyinnys
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 51

C++ Programming From Problem Analysis to Program

Design 8th Edition Malik Test Bank download

https://testbankdeal.com/product/c-programming-from-problem-
analysis-to-program-design-8th-edition-malik-test-bank/

Explore and download more test bank or solution manual


at testbankdeal.com
We believe these products will be a great fit for you. Click
the link to download now, or visit testbankdeal.com
to discover even more!

C++ Programming From Problem Analysis to Program Design


8th Edition Malik Solutions Manual

https://testbankdeal.com/product/c-programming-from-problem-analysis-
to-program-design-8th-edition-malik-solutions-manual/

C++ Programming From Problem Analysis to Program Design


7th Edition Malik Test Bank

https://testbankdeal.com/product/c-programming-from-problem-analysis-
to-program-design-7th-edition-malik-test-bank/

C++ Programming From Problem Analysis to Program Design


6th Edition Malik Test Bank

https://testbankdeal.com/product/c-programming-from-problem-analysis-
to-program-design-6th-edition-malik-test-bank/

Mathematics for Elementary School Teachers 6th Edition


Bassarear Solutions Manual

https://testbankdeal.com/product/mathematics-for-elementary-school-
teachers-6th-edition-bassarear-solutions-manual/
Network Management Principles and Practices 2nd Edition
Subramanian Solutions Manual

https://testbankdeal.com/product/network-management-principles-and-
practices-2nd-edition-subramanian-solutions-manual/

Abnormal Psychology 16th Edition Butcher Test Bank

https://testbankdeal.com/product/abnormal-psychology-16th-edition-
butcher-test-bank/

Operations Management Processes and Supply Chains 12th


Edition Krajewski Solutions Manual

https://testbankdeal.com/product/operations-management-processes-and-
supply-chains-12th-edition-krajewski-solutions-manual/

Microbiology Fundamentals A Clinical Approach 3rd Edition


Cowan Test Bank

https://testbankdeal.com/product/microbiology-fundamentals-a-clinical-
approach-3rd-edition-cowan-test-bank/

Illustrated Microsoft Office 365 and Office 2016


Fundamentals 1st Edition Hunt Solutions Manual

https://testbankdeal.com/product/illustrated-microsoft-office-365-and-
office-2016-fundamentals-1st-edition-hunt-solutions-manual/
Issues in Financial Accounting 15th Edition Henderson Test
Bank

https://testbankdeal.com/product/issues-in-financial-accounting-15th-
edition-henderson-test-bank/
Name: Class: Date:

Chapter 10
1. A class is an example of a structured data type.
a. True
b. False
ANSWER: True
POINTS: 1
REFERENCES: 652
QUESTION TYPE: True / False
HAS VARIABLES: False
DATE CREATED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
DATE MODIFIED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM

2. In C++, class is a reserved word and it defines only a data type.


a. True
b. False
ANSWER: True
POINTS: 1
REFERENCES: 653
QUESTION TYPE: True / False
HAS VARIABLES: False
DATE CREATED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
DATE MODIFIED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM

3. If the heading of a member function of a class ends with the word const, then the function member cannot modify the
private member variables, but it can modify the public member variables.
a. True
b. False
ANSWER: False
POINTS: 1
REFERENCES: 655
QUESTION TYPE: True / False
HAS VARIABLES: False
DATE CREATED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
DATE MODIFIED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM

4. In C++ terminology, a class object is the same as a class instance.


a. True
b. False
ANSWER: True
POINTS: 1
REFERENCES: 656
QUESTION TYPE: True / False
HAS VARIABLES: False
DATE CREATED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
Copyright Cengage Learning. Powered by Cognero. Page 1
Name: Class: Date:

Chapter 10
DATE MODIFIED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM

5. Given this declaration:


class myClass
{
public:
void print(); //Output the value of x;
MyClass();

private:
int x;
};

myClass myObject;

The following statement is legal.


myObject.x = 10;
a. True
b. False
ANSWER: False
POINTS: 1
REFERENCES: 657
QUESTION TYPE: True / False
HAS VARIABLES: False
DATE CREATED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
DATE MODIFIED: 10/30/2016 12:12 PM

6. If an object is declared in the definition of a member function of the class, then the object can access both the public
and private members of the class.
a. True
b. False
ANSWER: True
POINTS: 1
REFERENCES: 657
QUESTION TYPE: True / False
HAS VARIABLES: False
DATE CREATED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
DATE MODIFIED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM

7. If an object is created in a user program, then the object can access both the public and private members of the
class.
a. True
b. False
ANSWER: False
POINTS: 1

Copyright Cengage Learning. Powered by Cognero. Page 2


Name: Class: Date:

Chapter 10
REFERENCES: 657
QUESTION TYPE: True / False
HAS VARIABLES: False
DATE CREATED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
DATE MODIFIED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM

8. You can use arithmetic operators to perform arithmetic operations on class objects.
a. True
b. False
ANSWER: False
POINTS: 1
REFERENCES: 659
QUESTION TYPE: True / False
HAS VARIABLES: False
DATE CREATED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
DATE MODIFIED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM

9. As parameters to a function, class objects can be passed by reference only.


a. True
b. False
ANSWER: False
POINTS: 1
REFERENCES: 660
QUESTION TYPE: True / False
HAS VARIABLES: False
DATE CREATED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
DATE MODIFIED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM

10. The public members of a class must be declared before the private members.
a. True
b. False
ANSWER: False
POINTS: 1
REFERENCES: 670
QUESTION TYPE: True / False
HAS VARIABLES: False
DATE CREATED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
DATE MODIFIED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM

11. The components of a class are called the ____ of the class.
a. elements b. members
c. objects d. properties
ANSWER: b
Copyright Cengage Learning. Powered by Cognero. Page 3
Name: Class: Date:

Chapter 10
POINTS: 1
REFERENCES: 652
QUESTION TYPE: Multiple Choice
HAS VARIABLES: False
DATE CREATED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
DATE MODIFIED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM

12. Which of the following class definitions is correct in C++?

a. class studentType
{
public:
void setData(string, double, int);
private:
string name;
};

b. class studentType
{
public:
void setData(string, double, int);
void print() const;
private:
string name;
double gpa;
}

c. class studentType
{
public void setData(string, double, int);
private string name;
};

d. studentType class
{
public: void setData(string, double, int);
private: string name;
};

ANSWER: a
POINTS: 1
REFERENCES: 654
QUESTION TYPE: Multiple Choice
HAS VARIABLES: False
DATE CREATED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
DATE MODIFIED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM

13. If a member of a class is ____, you cannot access it outside the class.
Copyright Cengage Learning. Powered by Cognero. Page 4
Name: Class: Date:

Chapter 10
a. public b. automatic
c. private d. static
ANSWER: c
POINTS: 1
REFERENCES: 654
QUESTION TYPE: Multiple Choice
HAS VARIABLES: False
DATE CREATED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
DATE MODIFIED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM

14. A class and its members can be described graphically using a notation known as the ____ notation.
a. OON b. OOD
c. UML d. OOP
ANSWER: c
POINTS: 1
REFERENCES: 656
QUESTION TYPE: Multiple Choice
HAS VARIABLES: False
DATE CREATED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
DATE MODIFIED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM

clockType
-hr: int
-min: int
-sec: int
+setTime(int, int, int): void
+getTime(int&, int&, int&) const: void
+printTime() const: void
+incrementSeconds(): int
+incrementMinutes(): int
+incrementHours(): int
+equalTime(const clockType&) const: bool

15. The word ____ at the end of several the member functions in the accompanying figure class clockType specifies
that these functions cannot modify the member variables of a clockType object.
a. static b. const
c. automatic d. private
ANSWER: b
POINTS: 1
REFERENCES: 655
QUESTION TYPE: Multiple Choice
HAS VARIABLES: False
PREFACE NAME: clockType definition
DATE CREATED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
DATE MODIFIED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
Copyright Cengage Learning. Powered by Cognero. Page 5
Name: Class: Date:

Chapter 10

16. Consider the UML class diagram shown in the accompanying figure. Which of the following is the name of the class?
a. clock b. clockType
c. Type d. +clockType
ANSWER: b
POINTS: 1
REFERENCES: 656
QUESTION TYPE: Multiple Choice
HAS VARIABLES: False
PREFACE NAME: clockType definition
DATE CREATED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
DATE MODIFIED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM

17. Consider the UML class diagram shown in the accompanying figure. According to the UML class diagram, how many
private members are in the class?
a. none b. zero
c. two d. three
ANSWER: d
POINTS: 1
REFERENCES: 656
QUESTION TYPE: Multiple Choice
HAS VARIABLES: False
PREFACE NAME: clockType definition
DATE CREATED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
DATE MODIFIED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM

18. A ____ sign in front of a member name on a UML diagram indicates that this member is a public member.
a. + b. -
c. # d. $
ANSWER: a
POINTS: 1
REFERENCES: 656
QUESTION TYPE: Multiple Choice
HAS VARIABLES: False
DATE CREATED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
DATE MODIFIED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM

19. A ____ sign in front of a member name on a UML diagram indicates that this member is a protected member.
a. + b. -
c. # d. $
ANSWER: c
POINTS: 1
REFERENCES: 656
Copyright Cengage Learning. Powered by Cognero. Page 6
Name: Class: Date:

Chapter 10
QUESTION TYPE: Multiple Choice
HAS VARIABLES: False
DATE CREATED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
DATE MODIFIED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM

class rectangleType
{
public:
void setLengthWidth(double x, double y);
//Postcondition: length = x; width = y;
void print() const;
//Output length and width;
double area();
//Calculate and return the area of the rectangle;
double perimeter();
//Calculate and return the parameter;
rectangleType();
//Postcondition: length = 0; width = 0;
rectangleType(double x, double y);
//Postcondition: length = x; width = y;

private:
double length;
double width;
};

20. Consider the accompanying class definition. Which of the following variable declarations is correct?
a. rectangle rectangleType;
b. class rectangleType rectangle;
c. rectangleType rectangle;
d. rectangle rectangleType.area;
ANSWER: c
POINTS: 1
REFERENCES: 657
QUESTION TYPE: Multiple Choice
HAS VARIABLES: False
PREFACE NAME: rectangleType class
DATE CREATED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
DATE MODIFIED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM

21. Consider the accompanying class definition, and the declaration:

rectangleType bigRect;

Which of the following statements is correct?


a. rectangleType.print(); b. rectangleType::print();
c. bigRect.print(); d. bigRect::print();
ANSWER: c
Copyright Cengage Learning. Powered by Cognero. Page 7
Name: Class: Date:

Chapter 10
POINTS: 1
REFERENCES: 657
QUESTION TYPE: Multiple Choice
HAS VARIABLES: False
PREFACE NAME: rectangleType class
DATE CREATED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
DATE MODIFIED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM

22. Consider the accompanying class definition, and the object declaration:

rectangleType bigRect(14,10);

Which of the following statements is correct?


a. bigRect.setLengthWidth();
b. bigRect.setLengthWidth(3.0, 2.0);
c. bigRect.length = 2.0;
d. bigRect.length = bigRect.width;
ANSWER: b
POINTS: 1
REFERENCES: 658
QUESTION TYPE: Multiple Choice
HAS VARIABLES: False
PREFACE NAME: rectangleType class
DATE CREATED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
DATE MODIFIED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM

23. In C++, the ____ is called the member access operator.


a. . b. ,
c. :: d. #
ANSWER: a
POINTS: 1
REFERENCES: 657
QUESTION TYPE: Multiple Choice
HAS VARIABLES: False
DATE CREATED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
DATE MODIFIED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM

24. A class object can be ____. That is, it is created each time the control reaches its declaration, and destroyed when
the control exits the surrounding block.
a. static b. automatic
c. local d. public
ANSWER: b
POINTS: 1

Copyright Cengage Learning. Powered by Cognero. Page 8


Name: Class: Date:

Chapter 10
REFERENCES: 660
QUESTION TYPE: Multiple Choice
HAS VARIABLES: False
DATE CREATED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
DATE MODIFIED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM

25. A class object can be ____. That is, it can be created once, when the control reaches its declaration, and destroyed
when the program terminates.
a. static b. automatic
c. local d. public
ANSWER: a
POINTS: 1
REFERENCES: 660
QUESTION TYPE: Multiple Choice
HAS VARIABLES: False
DATE CREATED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
DATE MODIFIED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM

26. In C++, you can pass a variable by reference and still prevent the function from changing its value by using the
keyword ____ in the formal parameter declaration.
a. automatic b. private
c. static d. const
ANSWER: d
POINTS: 1
REFERENCES: 660
QUESTION TYPE: Multiple Choice
HAS VARIABLES: False
DATE CREATED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
DATE MODIFIED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM

27. In C++, the scope resolution operator is ____.


a. : b. ::
c. $ d. .
ANSWER: b
POINTS: 1
REFERENCES: 662
QUESTION TYPE: Multiple Choice
HAS VARIABLES: False
DATE CREATED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
DATE MODIFIED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM

28. A member function of a class that only accesses the value(s) of the data member(s) is called a(n) ____ function.
a. accessor b. mutator

Copyright Cengage Learning. Powered by Cognero. Page 9


Name: Class: Date:

Chapter 10
c. constructor d. destructor
ANSWER: a
POINTS: 1
REFERENCES: 666
QUESTION TYPE: Multiple Choice
HAS VARIABLES: False
DATE CREATED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
DATE MODIFIED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM

29. To guarantee that the member variables of a class are initialized, you use ____.
a. accessors b. mutators
c. constructors d. destructor
ANSWER: c
POINTS: 1
REFERENCES: 671
QUESTION TYPE: Multiple Choice
HAS VARIABLES: False
DATE CREATED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
DATE MODIFIED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM

class secretType
{
public:
static int count;
static int z;

secretType();
secretType(int a);
void print();
static void incrementY();

private:
int x;
static int y;
};

secretType::secretType()
{
x = 1;
}

secretType::secretType(int a)
{
x = a;
}

void secretType::print()
{
Copyright Cengage Learning. Powered by Cognero. Page 10
Visit https://testbankdead.com
now to explore a rich
collection of testbank,
solution manual and enjoy
exciting offers!
Name: Class: Date:

Chapter 10
cout << "x = " << x << ", y = " << y
<< "z = " << z
<< ", count = " << count << endl;
}

static void secretType::incrementY()


{
y++;
}

30. Consider the accompanying class and member functions definitions. How many constructors are present in the class
definition?
a. none b. one
c. two d. three
ANSWER: c
POINTS: 1
REFERENCES: 672
QUESTION TYPE: Multiple Choice
HAS VARIABLES: False
PREFACE NAME: secretType class
DATE CREATED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
DATE MODIFIED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM

31. How many destructors can a class have?


a. no explicit destructors b. one
c. two d. any number
ANSWER: b
POINTS: 1
REFERENCES: 681
QUESTION TYPE: Multiple Choice
HAS VARIABLES: False
DATE CREATED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
DATE MODIFIED: 10/30/2016 12:15 PM

32. A destructor has the character ____, followed by the name of the class.
a. . b. ::
c. # d. ˜
ANSWER: d
POINTS: 1
REFERENCES: 681
QUESTION TYPE: Multiple Choice
HAS VARIABLES: False
DATE CREATED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
DATE MODIFIED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM

Copyright Cengage Learning. Powered by Cognero. Page 11


Name: Class: Date:

Chapter 10
33. What does ADT stand for?
a. abstract definition type b. asynchronous data transfer
c. abstract data type d. alternative definition type
ANSWER: c
POINTS: 1
REFERENCES: 682
QUESTION TYPE: Multiple Choice
HAS VARIABLES: False
DATE CREATED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
DATE MODIFIED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM

34. Which of the following is true about classes and structs?


a. By default, all members of a struct are public and all members of a class are private.
b. A struct variable is passed by value only, and a class variable is passed by reference only.
c. An assignment operator is allowed on class variables, but not on struct variables.
d. You cannot use the member access specifier private in a struct.
ANSWER: a
POINTS: 1
REFERENCES: 685
QUESTION TYPE: Multiple Choice
HAS VARIABLES: False
DATE CREATED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
DATE MODIFIED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM

35. If a function of a class is static, it is declared in the class definition using the keyword static in its ____.
a. return type b. parameters
c. heading d. main function
ANSWER: c
POINTS: 1
REFERENCES: 701
QUESTION TYPE: Multiple Choice
HAS VARIABLES: False
DATE CREATED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
DATE MODIFIED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM

36. With ____________________ functions, the definitions of the member functions are placed in the implementations
file.
ANSWER: inline
POINTS: 1
REFERENCES: 700
QUESTION TYPE: Completion
HAS VARIABLES: False
DATE CREATED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
Copyright Cengage Learning. Powered by Cognero. Page 12
Name: Class: Date:

Chapter 10
DATE MODIFIED: 10/30/2016 12:22 PM

37. If a class object is passed by ____________________, the contents of the member variables of the actual parameter
are copied into the corresponding member variables of the formal parameter.
ANSWER: value
POINTS: 1
REFERENCES: 660
QUESTION TYPE: Completion
HAS VARIABLES: False
DATE CREATED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
DATE MODIFIED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM

38. Non-static member variables of a class are called the ____________________ variables of the class.
ANSWER: instance
POINTS: 1
REFERENCES: 666
QUESTION TYPE: Completion
HAS VARIABLES: False
DATE CREATED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
DATE MODIFIED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM

39. A program or software that uses and manipulates the objects of a class is called a(n) ____________________ of that
class.
ANSWER: client
POINTS: 1
REFERENCES: 666
QUESTION TYPE: Completion
HAS VARIABLES: False
DATE CREATED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
DATE MODIFIED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM

40. A(n) ____________________ function of a class changes the values of the member variable(s) of the class.
ANSWER: mutator
POINTS: 1
REFERENCES: 666
QUESTION TYPE: Completion
HAS VARIABLES: False
DATE CREATED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
DATE MODIFIED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM

41. A(n) ____________________ contains the definitions of the functions to implement the operations of an object.
ANSWER: implementation file
POINTS: 1
REFERENCES: 686
Copyright Cengage Learning. Powered by Cognero. Page 13
Name: Class: Date:

Chapter 10
QUESTION TYPE: Completion
HAS VARIABLES: False
DATE CREATED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
DATE MODIFIED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM

42. The header file is also known as the ____________________.


ANSWER: interface file
interface
POINTS: 1
REFERENCES: 686
QUESTION TYPE: Completion
HAS VARIABLES: False
DATE CREATED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
DATE MODIFIED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM

43. A(n) ____________________ is a statement specifying the condition(s) that must be true before the function is called.
ANSWER: precondition
POINTS: 1
REFERENCES: 687
QUESTION TYPE: Completion
HAS VARIABLES: False
DATE CREATED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM
DATE MODIFIED: 10/5/2016 1:41 PM

Copyright Cengage Learning. Powered by Cognero. Page 14


Other documents randomly have
different content
Athenian scouts without: moreover, so conspicuous was the interior
of the city to spectators without, that the temple of Athênê, and
Brasidas with its ministers around him, performing the ceremony of
sacrifice, was distinctly recognized. The fact was made known to
Kleon as he stood on the high ridge taking his survey, while at the
same time those who had gone near to the gates reported that the
feet of many horses and men were beginning to be seen under
them, as if preparing for a sally.[742] He himself went close to the
gate, and satisfied himself of this circumstance: we must recollect
that there was no defender on the walls, and no danger from
missiles. Anxious to avoid coming to any real engagement before his
reinforcements should arrive, he at once gave orders for retreat,
which he thought might be accomplished before the attack from
within could be fully organized; for he imagined that a considerable
number of troops would be marched out, and ranged in battle order,
before the attack was actually begun, not dreaming that the sally
would be instantaneous, made with a mere handful of men. Orders
having been proclaimed to wheel to the left, and retreat in column
on the left flank towards Eion, Kleon, who was himself on the top of
the hill with the right wing, waited only to see his left and centre
actually in march on the road to Eion, and then directed his right
also to wheel to the left and follow them.
The whole Athenian army were thus in full retreat, marching in a
direction nearly parallel to the Long Wall of Amphipolis, with their
right or unshielded side exposed to the enemy, when Brasidas,
looking over the southernmost gates of the Long Wall with his small
detachment ready marshalled near him, burst out into contemptuous
exclamations on the disorder of their array.[743] “These men will not
stand us; I see it by the quivering of their spears and of their heads.
Men who reel about in that way, never stand an assailing enemy.
Open the gates for me instantly, and let us sally out with
confidence.”
With that, both the gate of the Long Wall nearest to the palisade,
and the adjoining gate of the palisade itself, were suddenly thrown
open, and Brasidas with his one hundred and fifty chosen soldiers
issued out through them to attack the retreating Athenians. Running
rapidly down the straight road which joined laterally the road
towards Eion along which the Athenians were marching, he charged
their central division on the right flank:[744] their left wing had
already got beyond him on the road towards Eion. Taken completely
unprepared, conscious of their own disorderly array, and astounded
at the boldness of their enemy, the Athenians of the centre were
seized with panic, made not the least resistance, and presently fled.
Even the Athenian left, though not attacked at all, instead of halting
to lend assistance, shared the panic and fled in disorder. Having thus
disorganized this part of the army, Brasidas passed along the line to
press his attack on the Athenian right: but in this movement he was
mortally wounded and carried off the field, unobserved by his
enemies. Meanwhile Klearidas, sallying forth from the Thracian gate,
had attacked the Athenian right on the ridge opposite to him,
immediately after it began its retreat. But the soldiers on the
Athenian right had probably seen the previous movement of Brasidas
against the other division, and though astonished at the sudden
danger, had thus a moment’s warning, before they were themselves
assailed, to halt and take close rank on the hill. Klearidas here found
a considerable resistance, in spite of the desertion of Kleon; who,
more astonished than any man in his army by a catastrophe so
unlooked for, lost his presence of mind and fled at once; but was
overtaken by a Thracian peltast from Myrkinus and slain. His soldiers
on the right wing, however, repelled two or three attacks in front
from Klearidas, and maintained their ground, until at length the
Chalkidian cavalry and the peltasts from Myrkinus, having come forth
out of the gates, assailed them with missiles in flank and rear so as
to throw them into disorder. The whole Athenian army was thus put
to flight; the left hurrying to Eion, the men of the right dispersing
and seeking safety among the hilly grounds of Pangæus in their rear.
Their sufferings and loss in the flight, from the hands of the pursuing
peltasts and cavalry, were most severe: and when they at last again
mustered at Eion, not only the commander Kleon, but six hundred
Athenian hoplites, half of the force sent out, were found missing.[745]
So admirably had the attack been concerted, and so entire was
its success, that only seven men perished on the side of the victors.
But of those seven, one was the gallant Brasidas himself, who being
carried into Amphipolis, lived just long enough to learn the complete
victory of his troops and then expired. Great and bitter was the
sorrow which his death occasioned throughout Thrace, especially
among the Amphipolitans. He received, by special decree, the
distinguished honor of interment within their city, the universal habit
being to inter even the most eminent deceased persons in a suburb
without the walls. All the allies attended his funeral in arms and with
military honors: his tomb was encircled by a railing, and the space
immediately fronting it was consecrated as the great agora of the
city, which was remodelled accordingly. He was also proclaimed
œkist, or founder, of Amphipolis, and as such, received heroic
worship with annual games and sacrifices to his honor.[746] The
Athenian Agnon, the real founder and originally recognized œkist of
the city, was stripped of all his commemorative honors and
expunged from the remembrance of the people: his tomb and the
buildings connected with it, together with every visible memento of
his name, being destroyed. Full of hatred as the Amphipolitans now
were towards Athens,—and not merely of hatred, but of fear, since
the loss which they had just sustained of their saviour and protector,
—they felt repugnance to the idea of rendering farther worship to an
Athenian œkist. Nor was it convenient to keep up such a religious
link with Athens, now that they were forced to look anxiously to
Lacedæmon for assistance. Klearidas, as governor of Amphipolis,
superintended those numerous alterations in the city which this
important change required, together with the erection of the trophy,
just at the spot where Brasidas had first charged the Athenians;
while the remaining armament of Athens, having obtained the usual
truce and buried their dead, returned home without farther
operations.
There are few battles recorded in history wherein the disparity
and contrast of the two generals opposed has been so manifest,—
consummate skill and courage on the one side against ignorance and
panic on the other. On the singular ability and courage of Brasidas
there can be but one verdict of unqualified admiration: but the
criticism passed by Thucydidês on Kleon, here as elsewhere, cannot
be adopted without reserves. He tells us that Kleon undertook his
march, from Eion up to the hill in front of Amphipolis, in the same
rash and confident spirit with which he had embarked on the
enterprise against Pylus, in the blind confidence that no one would
resist him.[747] Now I have already, in a former chapter, shown
grounds for concluding that the anticipations of Kleon respecting the
capture of Sphakteria, far from being marked by any spirit of
unmeasured presumption, were sober and judicious, realized to the
letter without any unlooked-for aid from fortune. Nor are the
remarks, here made by Thucydidês on that affair, more reasonable
than the judgment on it in his former chapter; for it is not true, as
he here implies, that Kleon expected no resistance in Sphakteria: he
calculated on resistance, but knew that he had force sufficient to
overcome it. His fault even at Amphipolis, great as that fault was,
did not consist in rashness and presumption. This charge at least is
rebutted by the circumstance, that he himself wished to make no
aggressive movement until his reinforcements should arrive, and
that he was only constrained, against his own will, to abandon his
intended temporary inactivity during that interval, by the angry
murmurs of his soldiers, who reproached him with ignorance and
backwardness, the latter quality being the reverse of that with which
he is branded by Thucydidês.
When Kleon was thus driven to do something, his march up to
the top of the hill, for the purpose of reconnoitring the ground, was
not in itself unreasonable, and might have been accomplished in
perfect safety, if he had kept his army in orderly array, prepared for
contingencies. But he suffered himself to be completely out-
generalled and overreached by that simulated consciousness of
impotence and unwillingness to fight, which Brasidas took care to
present to him. Among all military stratagems, this has perhaps been
the most frequently practised with success against inexperienced
generals, who are thrown off their guard and induced to neglect
precaution, not because they are naturally more rash or
presumptuous than ordinary men, but because nothing except either
a high order of intellect, or special practice and training, will enable
a man to keep steadily present to his mind liabilities even real and
serious, when there is no discernible evidence to suggest their
approach; much more when there is positive evidence, artfully laid
out by a superior enemy, to create belief in their absence. A fault
substantially the same had been committed by Thucydidês himself
and his colleague Euklês a year and a half before, when they
suffered Brasidas to surprise the Strymonian bridge and Amphipolis:
not even taking common precautions, nor thinking it necessary to
keep the fleet at Eion. They were not men peculiarly rash and
presumptuous, but ignorant and unpractised, in a military sense;
incapable of keeping before them dangerous contingencies which
they perfectly knew, simply because there was no present evidence
of approaching explosion.
This military incompetence, which made Kleon fall into the trap
laid for him by Brasidas, also made him take wrong measures
against the danger, when he unexpectedly discovered at last that the
enemy within were preparing to attack him. His fatal error consisted
in giving instant order for retreat, under the vain hope that he could
get away before the enemy’s attack could be brought to bear.[748] An
abler officer, before he commenced the retreating march so close to
the hostile walls, would have taken care to marshal his men in
proper array, to warn and address them with the usual harangue,
and to wind up their courage to the fighting-point: for up to that
moment they had no idea of being called upon to fight; and the
courage of Grecian hoplites, taken thus unawares while hurrying to
get away in disorder visible both to themselves and their enemies,
without any of the usual preliminaries of battle, was but too apt to
prove deficient. To turn the right or unshielded flank to the enemy,
was unavoidable from the direction of the retreating movement; nor
is it reasonable to blame Kleon for this, as some historians have
done, or for causing his right wing to move too soon in following the
lead of the left, as Dr. Arnold seems to think. The grand fault seems
to have consisted in not waiting to marshal his men and prepare
them for standing fight during their retreat. Let us add, however,
and the remark, if it serves to explain Kleon’s idea of being able to
get away before he was actually assailed, counts as a double
compliment to the judgment as well as boldness of Brasidas, that no
other Lacedæmonian general of that day perhaps, not even
Demosthenês, the most enterprising general of Athens, would have
ventured upon an attack with so very small a band, relying
altogether upon the panic produced by his sudden movement.
But the absence of military knowledge and precaution is not the
worst of Kleon’s faults on this occasion. His want of courage at the
moment of conflict is yet more lamentable, and divests his end of
that personal sympathy which would otherwise have accompanied it.
A commander who has been out-generalled is under a double force
of obligation to exert and expose himself, to the uttermost, in order
to retrieve the consequences of his own mistakes. He will thus at
least preserve his own personal honor, whatever censure he may
deserve on the score of deficient knowledge and judgment.[749]
What is said about the disgraceful flight of Kleon himself, must be
applied, with hardly less severity of criticism, to the Athenian
hoplites under him. They behaved in a manner altogether unworthy
of the reputation of their city; especially the left wing, which seems
to have broken and run away without waiting to be attacked. And
when we read in Thucydidês, that the men who thus disgraced
themselves were among the best, and the best-armed hoplites in
Athens; that they came out unwillingly under Kleon; that they began
their scornful murmurs against him before he had committed any
fault, despising him for backwardness when he was yet not strong
enough to attempt anything serious, and was only manifesting a
reasonable prudence in waiting the arrival of expected
reinforcements; when we read this, we shall be led to compare the
expedition against Amphipolis with former manœuvres respecting
the attack of Sphakteria, and to discern other causes for its failure
besides the military incompetence of the commander. These hoplites
brought out with them from Athens the feelings prevalent among the
political adversaries of Kleon. The expedition was proposed and
carried by him, contrary to their wishes: they could not prevent it,
but their opposition enfeebled it from the beginning, kept within too
narrow limits the force assigned to it, and was one main reason
which frustrated its success.
Had Periklês been alive, Amphipolis might perhaps still have been
lost, since its capture was the fault of the officers employed to
defend it. But if lost, it would probably have been attacked and
recovered with the same energy as the revolted Samos had been,
with the full force and the best generals that Athens could furnish.
With such an armament under good officers, there was nothing at all
impracticable in the reconquest of the place; especially as at that
time it had no defence on three sides except the Strymon, and might
thus be approached by Athenian ships on that navigable river. The
armament of Kleon,[750] even if his reinforcements had arrived, was
hardly sufficient for the purpose. But Periklês would have been able
to concentrate upon it the whole strength of the city, without being
paralyzed by the contentions of political party: he would have seen
as clearly as Kleon, that the place could only be recovered by force,
and that its recovery was the most important object to which Athens
could devote her energies.
It was thus that the Athenians, partly from political intrigue,
partly from the incompetence of Kleon, underwent a disastrous
defeat instead of carrying Amphipolis. But the death of Brasidas
converted their defeat into a substantial victory. There remained no
Spartan either like or second to that eminent man, either as a soldier
or a conciliating politician; none who could replace him in the
confidence and affection of the allies of Athens in Thrace; none who
could prosecute those enterprising plans against Athens on her
unshielded side, which he had first shown to be practicable. The
fears of Athens, and the hopes of Sparta, in respect to the future,
disappeared alike with him. The Athenian generals, Phormio and
Demosthenês, had both of them acquired among the Akarnanians an
influence personal to themselves, apart from their post and from
their country: but the career of Brasidas, exhibited an extent of
personal ascendency and admiration, obtained as well as deserved,
such as had never before been paralleled by any military chieftain in
Greece: and Plato might well select him as the most suitable
historical counterpart to the heroic Achilles.[751] All the achievements
of Brasidas were his own individually, with nothing more than bare
encouragement, sometimes even without encouragement, from his
country. And when we recollect the strict and narrow routine in
which as a Spartan he had been educated, so fatal to the
development of everything like original thought or impulse, and so
completely estranged from all experience of party or political
discussion, we are amazed at his resource and flexibility of character,
his power of adapting himself to new circumstances and new
persons, and his felicitous dexterity in making himself the rallying-
point of opposite political parties in each of the various cities which
he acquired. The combination “of every sort of practical excellence,”
valor, intelligence, probity, and gentleness of dealing, which his
character presented, was never forgotten among the subject-allies of
Athens, and procured for other Spartan officers in subsequent years
favorable presumptions, which their conduct was seldom found to
realize.[752] At the time when Brasidas perished, in the flower of his
age, he was unquestionably the first man in Greece; and though it is
not given to us to predict what he would have become had he lived,
we may be sure that the future course of the war would have been
sensibly modified; perhaps even to the advantage of Athens, since
she might have had sufficient occupation at home to keep her from
the disastrous enterprise in Sicily.
Thucydidês seems to take pleasure in setting forth the gallant
exploits of Brasidas, from the first at Methônê to the last at
Amphipolis, not less than the dark side of Kleon; both, though in
different senses, the causes of his banishment. He never mentions
the latter except in connection with some proceeding represented as
unwise or discreditable. The barbarities which the offended majesty
of empire thought itself entitled to practise in ancient times against
dependencies revolted and reconquered, reach their maximum in the
propositions against Mitylênê and Skiônê: both of them are ascribed
to Kleon by name as their author. But when we come to the
slaughter of the Melians, equally barbarous, and worse in respect to
grounds of excuse, inasmuch as the Melians had never been
subjects of Athens, we find Thucydidês mentioning the deed without
naming the proposer.[753]
Respecting the foreign policy of Kleon, the facts already narrated
will enable the reader to form an idea of it as compared with that of
his opponents. I have shown grounds for believing that Thucydidês
has forgotten his usual impartiality in criticizing this personal enemy;
that in regard to Sphakteria, Kleon was really one main and
indispensable cause of procuring for his country the greatest
advantage which she obtained throughout the whole war; and that
in regard to his judgment as advocating the prosecution of war,
three different times must be distinguished: 1. After the first
blockade of the hoplites in Sphakteria; 2. After the capture of the
island; 3. After the expiration of the one year truce. On the earliest
of those three occasions he was wrong, for he seems to have shut
the door on all possibilities of negotiation, by his manner of dealing
with the Lacedæmonian envoys. On the second occasion, he had fair
and plausible grounds to offer on behalf of his opinion, though it
turned out unfortunate: moreover, at that time, all Athens was
warlike, and Kleon is not to be treated as the peculiar adviser of that
policy. On the third and last occasion, after the expiration of the
truce, the political counsel of Kleon was right, judicious, and truly
Periklêan, much surpassing in wisdom that of his opponents. We
shall see in the coming chapters how those opponents managed the
affairs of the state after his death; how Nikias threw away the
interests of Athens in the enforcement of the conditions of peace;
how Nikias and Alkibiadês together shipwrecked the power of their
country on the shores of Syracuse. And when we judge the
demagogue Kleon in this comparison, we shall find ground for
remarking that Thucydidês is reserved and even indulgent towards
the errors and vices of other statesmen, harsh only towards those of
his accuser.
As to the internal policy of Kleon, and his conduct as a politician
in Athenian constitutional life, we have but little trustworthy
evidence. There exists, indeed, a portrait of him, drawn in colors
broad and glaring, most impressive to the imagination, and hardly
effaceable from the memory; the portrait in the “Knights” of
Aristophanês. It is through this representation that Kleon has been
transmitted to posterity, crucified by a poet who admits himself to
have had a personal grudge against him, just as he has been
commemorated in the prose of an historian whose banishment he
had proposed. Of all the productions of Aristophanês, so replete with
comic genius throughout, the “Knights” is the most consummate and
irresistible; the most distinct in its character, symmetry, and purpose.
Looked at with a view to the object of its author, both in reference to
the audience and to Kleon, it deserves the greatest possible
admiration, and we are not surprised to learn that it obtained the
first prize. It displays the maximum of that which wit combined with
malice can achieve, in covering an enemy with ridicule, contempt,
and odium. Dean Swift would have desired nothing worse, even for
Ditton and Winston. The old man, Demos of Pnyx, introduced on the
stage as personifying the Athenian people,—Kleon, brought on as his
newly-bought Paphlagonian slave, who by coaxing, lying, impudent
and false denunciation of others, has gained his master’s ear, and
heaps ill-usage upon every one else, while he enriches himself,—the
Knights, or chief members of what we may call the Athenian
aristocracy, forming the Chorus of the piece as Kleon’s pronounced
enemies,—the sausage-seller from the market-place, who, instigated
by Nikias find Demosthenês along with these Knights, overdoes
Kleon in all his own low arts, and supplants him in the favor of
Demos; all this, exhibited with inimitable vivacity of expression,
forms the masterpiece and glory of libellous comedy. The effect
produced upon the Athenian audience when this piece was
represented at the Lenæan festival, January B.C. 424, about six
months after the capture of Sphakteria, with Kleon himself and most
of the real Knights present, must have been intense beyond what we
can now easily imagine. That Kleon could maintain himself after this
humiliating exposure, is no small proof of his mental vigor and
ability. It does not seem to have impaired his influence, at least not
permanently; for not only do we see him the most effective
opponent of peace during the next two years, but there is ground for
believing that the poet himself found it convenient to soften his tone
towards this powerful enemy.
So ready are most writers to find Kleon guilty, that they are
satisfied with Aristophanês as a witness against him: though no
other public man, of any age or nation, has ever been condemned
upon such evidence. No man thinks of judging Sir Robert Walpole, or
Mr. Fox, or Mirabeau, from the numerous lampoons put in circulation
against them: no man will take measure of a political Englishman
from Punch, or of a Frenchman from the Charivari. The unrivalled
comic merit of the “Knights” of Aristophanês is only one reason the
more for distrusting the resemblance of its picture to the real Kleon.
We have means too of testing the candor and accuracy of
Aristophanês by his delineation of Sokratês, whom he introduced in
the comedy of “Clouds” in the year after that of the “Knights.” As a
comedy, the “Clouds” stands second only to the “Knights”: as a
picture of Sokratês, it is little better than pure fancy: it is not even a
caricature, but a totally different person. We may indeed perceive
single features of resemblance; the bare feet, and the argumentative
subtlety, belong to both; but the entire portrait is such, that if it bore
a different name, no one would think of comparing it with Sokratês,
whom we know well from other sources. With such an analogy
before us, not to mention what we know generally of the portraits of
Periklês by these authors, we are not warranted in treating the
portrait of Kleon as a likeness, except on points where there is
corroborative evidence. And we may add, that some of the hits
against him, where we can accidentally test their pertinence, are
decidedly not founded in fact; as, for example, where the poet
accuses Kleon of having deliberately and cunningly robbed
Demosthenês of his laurels in the enterprise against Sphakteria.[754]
In the prose of Thucydidês, we find Kleon described as a
dishonest politician, a wrongful accuser of others, the most violent of
all the citizens:[755] throughout the verse of Aristophanês, these
same charges are set forth with his characteristic emphasis, but
others are also superadded; Kleon practises the basest artifices and
deceptions to gain favor with the people, steals the public money,
receives bribes, and extorts compositions from private persons by
wholesale, and thus enriches himself under pretence of zeal for the
public treasury. In the comedy of the Acharnians, represented one
year earlier than the Knights, the poet alludes with great delight to a
sum of five talents, which Kleon had been compelled “to disgorge”: a
present tendered to him by the insular subjects of Athens, if we may
believe Theopompus, for the purpose of procuring a remission of
their tribute, and which the Knights, whose evasions of military
service he had exposed, compelled him to relinquish.[756]
But when we put together the different heads of indictment
accumulated by Aristophanês, it will be found that they are not
easily reconcilable one with the other; for an Athenian, whose
temper led him to violent crimination of others, at the inevitable
price of multiplying and exasperating personal enemies, would find it
peculiarly dangerous, if not impossible, to carry on peculation for his
own account. If, on the other hand, he took the latter turn, he would
be inclined to purchase connivance from others even by winking at
real guilt on their part, far from making himself conspicuous as a
calumniator of innocence. We must therefore discuss the side of the
indictment which is indicated in Thucydidês; not Kleon, as truckling
to the people and cheating for his own pecuniary profit (which is
certainly not the character implied in his speech about the
Mitylenæans, as given to us by the historian),[757] but Kleon as a
man of violent temper and fierce political antipathies, a bitter
speaker, and sometimes dishonest in his calumnies against
adversaries. These are the qualities which, in all countries of free
debate, go to form what is called a great opposition speaker. It was
thus that the elder Cato, “the universal biter, whom Persephonê was
afraid even to admit into Hades after his death,” was characterized
at Rome, even by the admission of his admirers to some extent, and
in a still stronger manner by those who were unfriendly to him, as
Thucydidês was to Kleon.[758] In Cato, such a temper was not
inconsistent with a high sense of public duty. And Plutarch recounts
an anecdote respecting Kleon, that, on first beginning his political
career, he called his friends together, and dissolved his intimacy with
them, conceiving that private friendships would distract him from his
paramount duty to the commonwealth.[759]
Moreover, the reputation of Kleon as a frequent and unmeasured
accuser of others, may be explained partly by a passage of his
enemy Aristophanês: a passage the more deserving of confidence as
a just representation of fact, since it appears in a comedy (the
“Frogs”) represented (405 B.C.) fifteen years after the death of Kleon,
and five years after that of Hyperbolus, when the poet had less
motive for misrepresentations against either. In the “Frogs,” the
scene is laid in Hades, whither the god Dionysus goes, in the attire
of Hêraklês and along with his slave Xanthias, for the purpose of
bringing up again to earth the deceased poet Euripidês. Among the
incidents, Xanthias, in the attire which his master had worn, is
represented as acting with violence and insult towards two hostesses
of eating-houses; consuming their substance, robbing them, refusing
to pay when called upon, and even threatening their lives with a
drawn sword. Upon which the women, having no other redress left,
announce their resolution of calling, the one upon her protector
Kleon, the other on Hyperbolus, for the purpose of bringing the
offender to justice before the dikastery.[760] This passage shows us,
if inferences on comic evidence are to be held as admissible, that
Kleon and Hyperbolus became involved in accusations partly by
helping poor persons who had been wronged to obtain justice before
the dikastery. A rich man who had suffered injury might apply to
Antipho or some other rhetor for paid advice and aid as to the
conduct of his complaint; but a poor man or woman would think
themselves happy to obtain the gratuitous suggestion, and
sometimes the auxiliary speech, of Kleon or Hyperbolus; who would
thus extend their own popularity, by means very similar to those
practised by the leading men in Rome.[761]
But besides lending aid to others, doubtless Kleon was often also
a prosecutor, in his own name, of official delinquents, real or alleged.
That some one should undertake this duty was indispensable for the
protection of the city; otherwise, the responsibility to which official
persons were subjected after their term of office would have been
merely nominal: and we have proof enough that the general public
morality of these official persons, acting individually, was by no
means high. But the duty was at the same time one which most
persons would and did shun. The prosecutor, while obnoxious to
general dislike, gained nothing even by the most complete success;
and if he failed so much as not to procure a minority of votes among
the dikasts, equal to one-fifth of the numbers present, he was
condemned to pay a fine of one thousand drachms. What was still
more serious, he drew upon himself a formidable mass of private
hatred, from the friends, partisans, and the political club, of the
accused party, extremely menacing to his own future security and
comfort, in a community like Athens. There was therefore little
motive to accept, and great motive to decline, the task of
prosecuting on public grounds. A prudent politician at Athens would
undertake it occasionally, and against special rivals, but he would
carefully guard himself against the reputation of doing it frequently
or by inclination, and the orators constantly do so guard themselves
in those speeches which yet remain.
It is this reputation which Thucydidês fastens upon Kleon, and
which, like Cato the censor at Rome, he probably merited; from
native acrimony of temper, from a powerful talent for invective and
from his position, both inferior and hostile to the Athenian knights,
or aristocracy, who overshadowed him by their family importance.
But in what proportion of cases his accusations were just or
calumnious, the real question upon which a candid judgment turns,
we have no means of deciding, either in his case or that of Cato. “To
lash the wicked (observes Aristophanês himself[762]) is not only no
blame, but is even a matter of honor to the good.” It has not been
common to allow to Kleon the benefit of this observation, though he
is much more entitled to it than Aristophanês. For the attacks of a
poetical libeller admit neither of defence nor retaliation; whereas a
prosecutor before the dikastery found his opponent prepared to
reply or even to retort, and was obliged to specify his charge, as well
as to furnish proof of it; so that there was a fair chance for the
innocent man not to be confounded with the guilty.
The quarrel of Kleon with Aristophanês is said to have arisen out
of an accusation which he brought against that poet[763] in the
Senate of Five Hundred, on the subject of his second comedy, the
“Babylonians,” exhibited B.C. 426, at the festival of the urban
Dionysia in the month of March. At that season many strangers were
present at Athens, and especially many visitors and deputies from
the subject-allies, who were bringing their annual tribute: and as the
“Babylonians,” (now lost), like so many other productions of
Aristophanês, was full of slashing ridicule, not only against individual
citizens but against the functionaries and institutions of the city,[764]
Kleon instituted a complaint against it in the senate, as an exposure
dangerous to the public security before strangers and allies. We
have to recollect that Athens was then in the midst of an
embarrassing war; that the fidelity of her subject-allies was much
doubted; that Lesbos, the greatest of her allies, had been
reconquered only in the preceding year, after a revolt both
troublesome and perilous to the Athenians. Under such
circumstances, Kleon had good reason for thinking that a political
comedy of the Aristophanic vein and talent tended to degrade the
city in the eyes of strangers, even granting that it was innocuous
when confined to the citizens themselves. The poet complains[765]
that Kleon summoned him before the senate, with terrible threats
and calumny: but it does not appear that any penalty was inflicted.
Nor, indeed, had the senate competence to find him guilty or punish
him except to the extent of a small fine: they could only bring him to
trial before the dikastery, which in this case plainly was not done. He
himself, however, seems to have felt the justice of the warning: for
we find that three out of his four next following plays, before the
Peace of Nikias,—the Acharnians, the Knights, and the Wasps,—were
represented at the Lenæan festival,[766] in the month of January, a
season when no strangers nor allies were present. Kleon was
doubtless much incensed with the play of the Knights, and seems to
have annoyed the poet either by bringing an indictment against him
for exercising freemen’s rights without being duly qualified, since
none but citizens were allowed to appear and act in the dramatic
exhibitions, or by some other means which are not clearly explained.
Nor can we make out in what way the poet met him, though it
appears that finding less public sympathy than he thought himself
entitled to, he made an apology without intending to be bound by it.
[767] Certain it is, that his remaining plays subsequent to the Knights,
though containing some few bitter jests against Kleon, manifest no
second deliberate set against him.
The battle of Amphipolis removed at once the two most
pronounced individual opponents of peace, Kleon and Brasidas.
Athens too was more than ever discouraged and averse to prolonged
fighting; for the number of hoplites slain at Amphipolis doubtless
filled the city with mourning, besides the unparalleled disgrace now
tarnishing Athenian soldiership. The peace-party under the auspices
of Nikias and Lachês, relieved at once from the internal opposition of
Kleon, as well as from the foreign enterprise of Brasidas, were
enabled to resume their negotiations with Sparta in a spirit
promising success. King Pleistoanax, and the Spartan ephors of the
year, were on their side equally bent on terminating the war, and the
deputies of all the allies were convoked at Sparta for discussion with
the envoys of Athens. Such discussion was continued during the
whole autumn and winter after the battle of Amphipolis, without any
actual hostilities on either side. At first, the pretensions advanced
were found very conflicting; but at length, after several debates, it
was agreed to treat upon the basis of each party surrendering what
had been acquired by war. The Athenians insisted at first on the
restoration of Platæa; but the Thebans replied that Platæa was
theirs neither by force nor by treason, but by voluntary capitulation
and surrender of the inhabitants. This distinction seems to our ideas
somewhat remarkable, since the capitulation of a besieged town is
not less the result of force than capture by storm. But it was
adopted in the present treaty; and under it the Athenians, while
foregoing their demand of Platæa, were enabled to retain Nisæa,
which they had acquired from the Megarians, and Anaktorium and
Sollium,[768] which they had taken from Corinth. To insure
accommodating temper on the part of Athens, the Spartans held out
the threat of invading Attica in the spring, and of establishing a
permanent fortification in the territory: and they even sent round
proclamation to their allies, enjoining all the details requisite for this
step. Since Attica had now been exempt from invasion for three
years, the Athenians were probably not insensible to this threat of
renewal under a permanent form.
At the beginning of spring, about the end of March, 421 B.C.,
shortly after the urban Dionysia at Athens, the important treaty was
concluded for the term of fifty years. The following were its principal
conditions:—
1. All shall have full liberty to visit all the public temples of
Greece, for purposes of private sacrifice, consultation of oracle, or
public sacred mission. Every man shall be undisturbed both in going
and coming. [The value of this article will be felt, when we recollect
that the Athenians and their allies had been unable to visit the
Olympic or Pythian festival since the beginning of the war.]
2. The Delphians shall enjoy full autonomy and mastery of their
temple and their territory. [This article was intended to exclude the
ancient claim of the Phocian confederacy to the management of the
temple; a claim which the Athenians had once supported, before the
thirty years’ truce: but they had now little interest in the matter,
since the Phocians were in the ranks of their enemies.]
3. There shall be peace for fifty years, between Athens and
Sparta with their respective allies, with abstinence from mischief,
either overt or fraudulent, by land as well as by sea.
4. Neither party shall invade for purposes of mischief the territory
of the other, not by any artifice or under any pretence.
Should any subject of difference arise, it shall be settled by
equitable means, and by oaths tendered and taken, in form to be
hereafter agreed on.
5. The Lacedæmonians and their allies shall restore Amphipolis to
the Athenians.
They shall farther relinquish to the Athenians Argilus, Stageirus,
Akanthus, Skôlus, Olynthus, and Spartôlus. But these cities shall
remain autonomous, on condition of paying tribute to Athens
according to the assessment of Aristeidês. Any of their citizens who
may choose to quit them shall be at liberty to do so, and to carry
away his property. Nor shall the cities be counted hereafter either as
allies of Athens or of Sparta, unless Athens shall induce them by
amicable persuasions to become her allies, which she is at liberty to
do if she can.
The inhabitants of Mekyberna, Sanê, and Singê, shall dwell
independently in their respective cities, just as much as the
Olynthians and Akanthians. [These were towns which adhered to
Athens, and were still numbered as her allies; though they were
near enough to be molested by Olynthus[769] and Akanthus, against
which this clause was intended to insure them.]
The Lacedæmonians and their allies shall also restore Panaktum
to the Athenians.
6. The Athenians shall restore to Sparta Koryphasium, Kythêra,
Methônê, Pteleum, Atalantê, with all the captives in their hands from
Sparta or her allies. They shall farther release all Spartans or allies of
Sparta now blocked up in Skiônê.
7. The Lacedæmonians and their allies shall also restore all the
captives in their hands, from Athens or her allies.
8. Respecting Skiônê, Torônê, Sermylus, or any other town in the
possession of Athens, the Athenians may take their own measures.
9. Oaths shall be exchanged between the contracting parties,
according to the solemnities held most binding in each city
respectively, and in the following words: “I will adhere to this
convention and truce sincerely and without fraud.” The oaths shall
be annually renewed, and the terms of peace shall be inscribed on
columns at Olympia, Delphi, and the Isthmus, as well as at Sparta
and Athens.
10. Should any matter have been forgotten in the present
convention, the Athenians and Lacedæmonians may alter it by
mutual understanding and consent, without being held to violate
their oaths.
These oaths were accordingly exchanged: they were taken by
seventeen principal Athenians, and as many Spartans, on behalf of
their respective countries, on the 26th day of the month Artemisius
at Sparta, and on the 24th day of Elaphebolion at Athens,
immediately after the urban Dionysia; Pleistolas being ephor
eponymus at Sparta, and Alkæus archon eponymus at Athens.
Among the Lacedæmonians swearing, are included the two kings
Agis and Pleistoanax, the ephor Pleistolas, and perhaps other
ephors, but this we do not know, and Tellis, the father of Brasidas.
Among the Athenians sworn, are comprised Nikias, Lachês, Agnon,
Lamachus, and Demosthenês.[770]
Such was the peace—commonly known by the name of the
Peace of Nikias—concluded in the beginning of the eleventh spring
of the war, which had just lasted ten full years. Its conditions were
put to the vote at Sparta, in the assembly of deputies from the
Lacedæmonian allies, the majority of whom accepted them: which,
according to the condition adopted and sworn to by every member
of the confederacy,[771] made it binding upon all. There was, indeed,
a special reserve allowed to any particular state in case of religious
scruple, arising out of the fear of offending some of their gods or
heroes, but, saving this reserve, the peace had been formally
acceded to by the decision of the confederates. But it soon appeared
how little the vote of the majority was worth, even when enforced
by the strong pressure of Lacedæmon herself, when the more
powerful members were among the dissentient minority. The
Bœotians, Megarians, and Corinthians, all refused to accept it; nor
does it seem that any deputies from the allies took the oath along
with the Lacedæmonian envoys; though the truce for a year, two
years before,[772] had been sworn to by Lacedæmonian, Corinthian,
Megarian, Sikyonian, and Epidaurian envoys.
The Corinthians were displeased because they did not recover
Sollium and Anaktorium; the Megarians, because they did not regain
Nisæa; the Bœotians, because they were required to surrender
Panaktum. In spite of the urgent solicitations of Sparta, the deputies
of all these powerful states not only denounced the peace as unjust,
and voted against it in the general assembly of allies, but refused to
accept it when the vote was carried, and went home to their
respective cities for instructions.[773]
Such were the conditions, and such the accompanying
circumstances, of the Peace of Nikias, which terminated, or
professed to terminate, the great Peloponnesian war, after a duration
of ten years. Its consequences and fruits, in many respects such as
were not anticipated by either of the concluding parties, will be seen
in my next volume.
FOOTNOTES
[1] Xenophon, Memorab. iii, 5, 18.

[2] Thucyd. v. 30: about the Spartan confederacy,—εἰρημένον, κύριον εἶναι,


ὅ,τι ἂν τὸ πλῆθος τῶν ξυμμάχων ψηφίσηται, ἢν μή τι θεῶν ἢ ἡρώων κώλυμα ᾖ.

[3] Thucyd. ii, 63. τῆς τε πόλεως ὑμᾶς εἰκὸς τῷ τιμωμένῳ ἀπὸ τοῦ ἄρχειν,
ᾧπερ ἅπαντες ἀγάλλεσθε, βοηθεῖν, καὶ μὴ φεύγειν τοὺς πόνους, ἢ μηδὲ τὰς τιμὰς
διώκειν, etc.

[4] Plutarch, Periklês, c. 12.

[5] Plutarch, Periklês, c. 11.

[6] Aristophan. Vesp. 707.

[7] The island of Kythêra was conquered by the Athenians from Sparta in 425
B.C., and the annual tribute then imposed upon it was four talents (Thucyd. iv,
57). In the Inscription No. 143, ap. Boeckh, Corp. Inscr., we find some names
enumerated of tributary towns, with the amount of tribute opposite to each, but
the stone is too much damaged to give us much information. Tyrodiza, in Thrace,
paid one thousand drachms: some other towns, or junctions of towns, not clearly
discernible, are rated at one thousand, two thousand, three thousand drachms,
one talent, and even ten talents. This inscription must be anterior to 415 B.C.,
when the tribute was converted into a five per cent. duty upon imports and
exports: see Boeckh, Public Econ. of Athens, and his Notes upon the above-
mentioned Inscription.
It was the practice of Athens not always to rate each tributary city separately,
but sometimes to join several in one collective rating; probably each responsible
for the rest. This seems to have provoked occasional remonstrances from the
allies, in some of which the rhetor, Antipho, was employed to furnish the speech
which the complainants pronounced before the dikastery: see Antipho ap.
Harpokration, v. Ἀπόταξις—Συντελεῖς. It is greatly to be lamented that the
orations composed by Antipho, for the Samothrakians and Lindians,—the latter
inhabiting one of the three separate towns in the island of Rhodes,—have not
been preserved.

[8] Xenophon, Anab. vii, 1, 27. οὐ μεῖον χιλίων ταλάντων: compare Boeckh,
Public Econ. of Athens, b. iii, ch. 7, 15, 19.

[9] Aristophan. Vesp. 660. τάλαντ᾽ ἐγγὺς δισχίλια.

[10] Very excellent writers on Athenian antiquity (Boeckh, Public Econ. of


Athens, c. 15, 19, b. iii; Schömann, Antiq. J. P. Att. sect. lxxiv; K. F. Hermann, Gr.
Staatsalterthümer, sect. 157: compare, however, a passage in Boeckh, ch. 17, p.
421, Eng. transl., where he seems to be of an opposite opinion) accept this
statement, that the tribute levied by Athenians upon her allies was doubled some
years after the commencement of the Peloponnesian war,—at which time it was
six hundred talents,—and that it came to amount to twelve hundred talents.
Nevertheless, I cannot follow them, upon the simple authority of Æschinês, and
the Pseudo-Andokidês (Æschin. De Fals. Legat. c. 54, p. 301; Andokidês, De
Pace, c. 1, and the same orator cont. Alkibiad. c. 4). For we may state pretty
confidently, that neither of the two orations here ascribed to Andokidês is
genuine: the oration against Alkibiadês most decidedly not genuine. There
remains, therefore, as an original evidence, only the passage of Æschinês, which
has, apparently, been copied by the author of the Oration De Pace, ascribed to
Andokidês. Now the chapter of Æschinês, which professes to furnish a general
but brief sketch of Athenian history for the century succeeding the Persian
invasion, is so full of historical and chronological inaccuracies, that we can hardly
accept it, when standing alone, as authority for any matter of fact. In a note on
the chapter immediately preceding, I have already touched upon its extraordinary
looseness of statement,—pointed out by various commentators, among them
particularly by Mr. Fynes Clinton: see above, chap. xlv, note 2, pp. 409-411, in the
preceding volume.
The assertion, therefore, that the tribute from the Athenian allies was raised
to the sum of twelve hundred talents annually, comes to us only from the orator
Æschinês as an original witness: and in him it forms part of a tissue of statements
alike confused and incorrect. But against it we have a powerful negative
argument,—the perfect silence of Thucydidês. Is it possible that that historian
would have omitted all notice of a step so very important in its effects, if Athens
had really adopted it? He mentions to us the commutation by Athens of the
tribute from her allies into a duty of five per cent. payable by them on their
exports and imports (vii, 28)—this was in the nineteenth year of the war, 413 B.C.
But anything like the duplication of the tribute all at once, would have altered
much more materially the relations between Athens and her allies and would have
constituted in the minds of the latter a substantive grievance, such as to
aggravate the motive for revolt in a manner which Thucydidês could hardly fail to
notice. The orator Æschinês refers the augmentation of the tribute, up to twelve
hundred talents, to the time succeeding the peace of Nikias: M. Boeckh (Public
Econ. of Athens, b. iii, ch. 15-19, pp. 400-434) supposes it to have taken place
earlier than the representation of the Vespæ of Aristophanês, that is, about three
years before that peace, or 423 B.C. But this would have been just before the
time of the expedition of Brasidas into Thrace, and his success in exciting revolt
among the dependencies of Athens: if Athens had doubled her tribute upon all
the allies, just before that expedition, Thucydidês could not have omitted to
mention it, as increasing the chances of success to Brasidas, and helping to
determine the resolutions of the Akanthians and others, which were by no means
adopted unanimously or without hesitation, to revolt.
In reference to the oration called that of Andokidês against Alkibiadês, I made
some remarks in the fourth volume of this History (vol. iv, ch. xxxi, p. 151),
tending to show it to be spurious and of a time considerably later than that to
which it purports to belong. I will here add one other remark, which appears to
me decisive, tending to the same conclusion.
The oration professes to be delivered in a contest of ostracism between Nikias,
Alkibiadês, and the speaker: one of the three, he says, must necessarily be
ostracized, and the question is, to determine which of the three: accordingly, the
speaker dwells upon many topics calculated to raise a bad impression of
Alkibiadês, and a favorable impression of himself.
Among the accusations against Alkibiadês, one is, that after having
recommended, in the assembly of the people, that the inhabitants of Melos
should be sold as slaves, he had himself purchased a Melian woman among the
captives, and had had a son by her: it was criminal, argues the speaker, to beget
offspring by a woman whose relations he had contributed to cause to be put to
death, and whose city he had contributed to ruin (c. 8).
Upon this argument I do not here touch, any farther than to bring out the
point of chronology. The speech, if delivered at all, must have been delivered, at
the earliest, nearly a year after the capture of Melos by the Athenians: it may be
of later date, but it cannot possibly be earlier.
Now Melos surrendered in the winter immediately preceding the great
expedition of the Athenians to Sicily in 415 B.C., which expedition sailed about
midsummer (Thucyd. v, 116; vi, 30). Nikias and Alkibiadês both went as
commanders of that expedition: the latter was recalled to Athens for trial on the
charge of impiety about three months afterwards, but escaped in the way home,
was condemned and sentenced to banishment in his absence, and did not return
to Athens until 407 B.C., long after the death of Nikias, who continued in
command of the Athenian armament in Sicily, enjoying the full esteem of his
countrymen, until its complete failure and ruin before Syracuse,—and perished
himself afterwards as a Syracusan prisoner.
Taking these circumstances together, it will at once be seen that there never
can have been any time, ten months or more after the capture of Melos, when
Nikias and Alkibiadês could have been exposed to a vote of ostracism at Athens.
The thing is absolutely impossible: and the oration in which such historical and
chronological incompatibilities are embodied, must be spurious: furthermore, it
must have been composed long after the pretended time of delivery, when the
chronological series of events had been forgotten.
I may add that the story of this duplication of the tribute by Alkibiadês is
virtually contrary to the statement of Plutarch, probably borrowed from Æschinês,
who states that the demagogues gradually increased (κατὰ μικρὸν) the tribute to
thirteen hundred talents (Plutarch, Aristeid. c. 24).

[11] Thucyd. ii, 13.

[12] Thucyd. i, 80. The foresight of the Athenian people, in abstaining from
immediate use of public money and laying it up for future wants, would be still
more conspicuously demonstrated, if the statement of Æschinês, the orator, were
true, that they got together seven thousand talents between the peace of Nikias
and the Sicilian expedition. M. Boeckh believes this statement, and says: “It is not
impossible that one thousand talents might have been laid by every year, as the
amount of tribute received was so considerable.” (Public Economy of Athens, ch.
xx. p. 446, Eng. Trans.) I do not believe the statement: but M. Boeckh and
others, who do admit it, ought in fairness to set it against the many remarks
which they pass in condemnation of the democratical prodigality.

[13] Thucyd. i. 122-143; ii, 13. The πεντηκοστὴ, or duty of two per cent.
upon imports and exports at the Peiræus, produced to the state a revenue of
thirty-six talents in the year in which it was farmed by Andokidês, somewhere
about 400 B.C., after the restoration of the democracy at Athens from its defeat
and subversion at the close of the Peloponnesian war (Andokidês de Mysteriis, c.
23, p. 65). This was at a period of depression in Athenian affairs, and when trade
was doubtless not near so good as it had been during the earlier part of the
Peloponnesian war.
It seems probable that this must have been the most considerable permanent
source of Athenian revenue next to the tribute; though we do not know what rate
of customs-duty was imposed at the Peiræus during the Peloponnesian war.
Comparing together the two passages of Xenophon (Republ. Ath. 1, 17, and
Aristophan. Vesp. 657), we may suppose that the regular and usual rate of duty
was one per cent. or one ἑκατοστὴ,—while in case of need this may have been
doubled or tripled.—τὰς πολλὰς ἑκατοστάς, (see Boeckh, b. iii, chs. 1-4, pp. 298-
318, Eng. Trans.) The amount of revenue derived even from this source, however,
can have borne no comparison to the tribute.

[14] By Periklês, Thucyd. ii, 63. By Kleon, Thucyd. iii, 37. By the envoys at
Melos, v, 89. By Euphemus, vi, 85. By the hostile Corinthians, i, 124 as a matter
of course.

[15] Plutarch, Periklês. c. 20.

[16] Plutarch, Kimon. c. 14.

[17] Plutarch, Periklês, c. 19, 20.

[18] Xenophon, Rep. Ath. ii, 16. τὴν μὲν οὐσίαν ταῖς νήσοις παρατίθενται,
πιστεύοντες τῇ ἀρχῇ τῇ κατὰ θάλασσαν· τὴν δὲ Ἀττικὴν γῆν περιορῶσι
τεμνομένην, γιγνώσκοντες ὅτι εἰ αὐτὴν ἐλεήσουσιν, ἑτέρων ἀγαθῶν μειζόνων
στερήσονται.
Compare also Xenophon (Memorabil. ii, 8, 1, and Symposion, iv, 31).

[19] See the case of the free laborer and the husbandman at Naxos, Plato,
Euthyphro, c. 3.

[20] Thucyd. i. 100.

[21] Thucyd. iv, 105; Marcellinus, Vit. Thucyd. c. 19. See Rotscher, Leben des
Thukydides, ch. i, 4, p. 96, who gives a genealogy of Thucydidês, as far as it can
be made out with any probability. The historian was connected by blood with
Miltiadês and Kimon, as well as with Olorus, king of one of the Thracian tribes,
whose daughter Hegesipylê was wife of Miltiadês, the conqueror of Marathon. In
this manner, therefore, he belonged to one of the ancient heroic families of
Athens, and even of Greece, being an Ækid through Ajax and Philæus (Marcellin.
c. 2).

[22] Thucyd. iv, 102; v, 6.

[23] Diodor. xii, 35.

[24] Diodor. xii, 11, 12; Strabo. vi, 264: Plutarch, Periklês, c. 22.

[25] The Athenians pretended to no subject allies beyond the Ionian gulf,
Thucyd. vi, 14: compare vi, 45, 104; vii, 34. Thucydidês does not even mention
Thurii, in his catalogue of the allies of Athens at the beginning of the
Peloponnesian war (Thucyd. ii, 15).

[26] Plutarch, Periklês, c. 11.

[27] Compare the speech of Nikias, in reference to the younger citizens and
partisans of Alkibiadês sitting together near the latter in the assembly,—οὓς ἐγὼ
ὁρῶν νῦν ἐνθάδε τῷ αὐτῷ ἀνδρὶ π α ρ α κ ε λ ε υ σ τ ο ὺ ς κ α θ η μ έ ν ο υ ς φοβοῦμαι,
καὶ τοῖς πρεσβυτέροις ἀντιπαρακελεύομαι μὴ καταισχυνθῆναι, εἴ τῴ τις
παρακάθηται τῶνδε, etc. (Thucyd. vi, 13.) See also Aristophanês, Ekklesiaz. 298,
seq., about partisans sitting near together.

[28] Plutarch, Periklês, c. 8. Ὅταν ἐγὼ καταβάλω παλαίων, ἐκεῖνος ἀντιλέγων


ὡς οὐ πέπτωκε, νικᾷ, καὶ μεταπείθει τοὺς ὁρῶντας.

[29] Plutarch, Periklês, c. 11. ἡ δ᾽ ἐκείνων ἅμιλλα καὶ φιλοτιμία τῶν ἀνδρῶν
βαθυτάτην τομὴν τεμοῦσα τῆς πόλεως, τὸ μὲν δῆμον, τὸ δ᾽ ὀλίγους ἐποίησε
καλεῖσθαι.

[30] Plutarch, Periklês, c. 12. διέβαλλον ἐν ταῖς ἐκκλησίαις βοῶντες, ὡς ὁ μὲν


δῆμος ἀδοξεῖ καὶ κακῶς ἀκούει τὰ κοινὰ τῶν Ἑλλήνων χρήματα πρὸς αὑτὸν ἐκ
Δήλου μεταγαγών, ἣ δ᾽ ἔνεστιν αὐτῷ πρὸς τοὺς ἐγκαλοῦντας εὐπρεπεστάτη τῶν
προφάσεων, δείσαντα τοὺς βαρβάρους ἐκεῖθεν ἀνελέσθαι καὶ φυλάττειν ἐν ὀχυρῷ
τὰ κοινά, ταύτην ἀνῄρηκε Περικλῆς, etc.
Compare the speech of the Lesbians, and their complaints against Athens, at
the moment of their revolt in the fourth year of the Peloponnesian war (Thucyd.
iii, 10); where a similar accusation is brought forward,—ἐπειδὴ δὲ ἑωρῶμεν
αὐτοὺς (the Athenians) τὴν μὲν τοῦ Μήδου ἔχθραν ἀνιέντας, τὴν δὲ τῶν
ξυμμάχων δούλωσιν ἐπαγομένους, etc.

[31] Plutarch, Periklês, c. 20.

[32] Thucyd. i, 10.

[33] Plutarch, Periklês, c. 11-14. Τέλος δὲ πρὸς τὸν Θουκυδίδην ε ἰ ς ἀ γ ῶ ν α


περὶ τοῦ ὀστράκου καταστὰς κ α ὶ δ ι α κ ι ν δ υ ν ε ύ σ α ς, ἐκεῖνον μὲν ἐξέβαλε,
κατέλυσε δὲ τὴν ἀντιτεταγμένην ἑταιρείαν. See, in reference to the principle of
the ostracism, a remarkable incident at Magnesia, between two political rivals,
Krêtinês and Hermeias: also the just reflections of Montesquieu, Esprit des Loix,
xxvi, c. 17; xxix, c. 7.

[34] Plutarch, Periklês, c. 16: the indication of time, however, is vague.

[35] Plato, Gorgias, p. 455, with Scholia; Plutarch, Periklês, c. 13:


Forchhammer, Topographie von Athen, in Kieler Philologische Studien, pp. 279-
282.

[36] Isokratês, Orat. vii: Areopagit. p. 153. c. 27.

[37] See Dikæarchus, Vit. Græciæ, Fragm. ed. Fuhr. p. 140: compare the
description of Platæa in Thucydidês, ii, 3.
All the older towns now existing in the Grecian islands are put together in this
same manner,—narrow, muddy, crooked ways,—few regular continuous lines of
houses: see Ross, Reisen in den Griechischen Inseln, Letter xxvii, vol. ii, p. 20.

[38] Aristotle, Politic. ii, 5, 1; Xenophon, Hellen. ii, 4, 1; Harpokration, v,


Ἱπποδάμεια.

[39] Diodor, xii, 9.

[40] Leake, Topography of Athens, Append. ii and iii, pp. 328-336, 2d edit.

[41] See Leake, Topography of Athens, 2d ed. p. 111, Germ. transl. O. Müller
(De Phidiæ Vitâ, p. 18) mentions no less than eight celebrated statues of Athênê,
by the hand of Pheidias,—four in the acropolis of Athens.

[42] Plutarch, Periklês, c. 13-15; O. Müller, De Phidiæ Vitâ, pp 34-60, also his
work, Archäologie der Kunst, sects. 108-113.

[43] Thucyd. i, 80. καὶ τοῖς ἄλλοις ἅπασιν ἄριστα ἐξήρτυνται, πλούτῳ τε ἰδίῳ
καὶ δημοσίῳ καὶ ναυσὶ καὶ ἵπποις καὶ ὅπλοις, καὶ ὄχλῳ ὅσος οὐκ ἐν ἄλλῳ ἑνί γε
χωρίῳ Ἑλληνικῷ ἐστὶν, etc.

[44] Plutarch, Periklês, c. 13.

[45] Thucyd. i, 10.

[46] See Leake, Topography of Athens, Append. iii, p. 329, 2d ed. Germ.
transl. Colonel Leake, with much justice, contends that the amount of two
thousand and twelve talents, stated by Harpokration out of Philochorus as the
cost of the Propylæa alone, must be greatly exaggerated. Mr. Wilkins
(Atheniensia, p. 84) expresses the same opinion; remarking that the transport of
marble from Pentelikus to Athens is easy and on a descending road.
Demetrius Phalereus (ap. Cicer. de Officiis, ii, 17) blamed Periklês for the large
sum expended upon the Propylæa; nor is it wonderful that he uttered this
censure, if he had been led to rate the cost of them at two thousand and twelve
talents.

[47] Valer. Maxim. i, 7, 2.

[48] Thucyd. ii, 13.

[49] Plutarch, Periklês, c. 17. Plutarch gives no precise date, and O. Müller
(De Phidiæ Vitâ, p. 9) places these steps for convocation of a congress before the
first war between Sparta and Athens and the battle of Tanagra,—i. e., before 460
B.C. But this date seems to me improbable: Thebes was not yet renovated in
power, nor had Bœotia as yet recovered from the fruits of her alliance with the
Persians; moreover, neither Athens nor Periklês himself seem to have been at that
time in a situation to conceive so large a project; which suits in every respect
much better for the later period, after the thirty years’ truce, but before the
Peloponnesian war.

[50] Thucyd. i, 115; viii, 76; Plutarch, Periklês, c. 28.

[51] Thucyd. i, 115; Plutarch, Periklês, c. 25. Most of the statements which
appear in this chapter of Plutarch—over and above the concise narrative of
Thucydidês—appear to be borrowed from exaggerated party stories of the day.
We need make no remark upon the story, that Periklês was induced to take the
side of Milêtus against Samos, by the fact that Aspasia was a native of Milêtus.
Nor is it at all more credible that the satrap Pissuthnês, from good-will towards
Samos, offered Periklês ten thousand golden staters as an inducement to spare
Samos. It may perhaps be true however, that the Samian oligarchy, and those
wealthy men whose children were likely to be taken as hostages, tried the effect
of large bribes upon the mind of Periklês, to prevail upon him not to alter the
government.

[52] Thucyd. i, 114, 115.

[53] Strabo, xiv, p. 638; Schol. Aristeidês, t. iii, p. 485, Dindorf.

[54] See the interesting particulars recounted respecting Sophoklês by the


Chian poet, Ion, who met and conversed with him during the course of this
expedition (Athenæus, xiii, p. 603). He represents the poet as uncommonly
pleasing and graceful in society, but noway distinguished for active capacity.
Sophoklês was at this time in peculiar favor, from the success of his tragedy,
Antigonê, the year before. See the chronology of these events discussed and
elucidated in Boeckh’s preliminary Dissertation to the Antigonê, c. 6-9.

[55] Diodor. xi, 27.

[56] Plutarch, Periklês, c. 26. Plutarch seems to have had before him
accounts respecting this Samian campaign, not only from Ephorus, Stesimbrotus,
and Duris, but also from Aristotle: and the statements of the latter must have
differed thus far from Thucydidês, that he affirmed Melissus the Samian general
to have been victorious over Periklês himself, which is not to be reconciled with
the narrative of Thucydidês.
The Samian historian, Duris, living about a century after this siege, seems to
have introduced many falsehoods respecting the cruelties of Athens: see Plutarch,
l. c.

[57] It appears very improbable that this Thucydidês can be the historian
himself. If it be Thucydidês son of Melêsias, we must suppose him to have been
restored from ostracism before the regular time,—a supposition indeed noway
inadmissible in itself, but which there is nothing else to countenance. The author
of the Life of Sophoklês, as well as most of the recent critics, adopt this opinion.
On the other hand, it may have been a third person named Thucydidês; for
the name seems to have been common, as we might guess from the two words
of which it is compounded. We find a third Thucydidês mentioned viii, 92—a
native of Pharsalus: and the biographer, Marcellinus seems to have read of many
persons so called (Θουκύδιδαι πολλοὶ, p. xvi, ed. Arnold). The subsequent history
of Thucydidês son of Melêsias, is involved in complete obscurity. We do not know
the incident to which the remarkable passage in Aristophanês (Acharn. 703)
alludes,—compare Vespæ, 946: nor can we confirm the statement which the
Scholiast cites from Idomeneus, to the effect that Thucydidês was banished and
fled to Artaxerxes: see Bergk. Reliq. Com. Att. p. 61.

[58] Thucyd. i, 117; Diodor. xii, 27, 28; Isokratês, De Permutat. Or. xv, sect.
118; Cornel. Nepos, Vit. Timoth. c. 1.
The assertion of Ephorus (see Diodorus, xii, 28, and Ephori Fragm. 117 ed.
Marx, with the note of Marx) that Periklês employed battering machines against
the town, under the management of the Klazomenian Artemon, was called in
question by Herakleidês Ponticus, on the ground that Artemon was a
contemporary of Anakreon, near a century before: and Thucydidês represents
Periklês to have captured the town altogether by blockade.

[59] Thucyd. i, 40, 41.

[60] Thucyd. viii, 21.

[61] Compare Wachsmuth, Hellenische Alterthumskunde, sect. 58, vol. ii, p.


82.

[62] See Westermann, Geschichte der Beredsamkeit in Griechenland und


Rom; Diodor. xi, 33; Dionys. Hal. A. R. v, 17.
Periklês, in the funeral oration preserved by Thucydidês (ii, 35-40), begins by
saying—Οἱ μὲν πολλοὶ τῶν ἐνθάδε εἰρηκότων ἤδη ἐπαινοῦσι τ ὸ ν π ρ ο σ θ έ ν τ α
τῷ νόμῳ τὸν λόγον τόνδε, etc.
The Scholiast, and other commentators—K. F. Weber and Westermann among
the number—make various guesses as to what celebrated man is here designated
as the introducer of the custom of a funeral harangue. The Scholiast says, Solon:
Weber fixes on Kimon: Westermann, on Aristeidês: another commentator on
Themistoklês. But we may reasonably doubt whether any one very celebrated
man is specially indicated by the words τὸν προσθέντα. To commend the
introducer of the practice, is nothing more than a phrase for commending the
practice itself.
[63] Some fragments of it seem to have been preserved, in the time of
Aristotle: see his treatise De Rhetoricâ, i, 7; iii, 10, 3.

[64] Compare the enthusiastic demonstrations which welcomed Brasidas at


Skiônê (Thucyd. iv, 121).

[65] Plutarch, Periklês, c. 28; Thucyd. ii, 34.

[66] A short fragment remaining from the comic poet Eupolis (Κόλακες, Fr.
xvi, p. 493, ed. Meineke), attests the anxiety at Athens about the Samian war,
and the great joy when the island was reconquered: compare Aristophan. Vesp.
283.

[67] Thucyd. iii, 37; ii, 63. See the conference, at the island of Melos in the
sixteenth year of the Peloponnesian war (Thucyd. v, 89, seq.), between the
Athenian commissioners and the Melians. I think, however, that this conference is
less to be trusted as based in reality, than the speeches in Thucydidês generally,
—of which more hereafter.

[68] Thucyd. iii, 47. Νῦν μὲν γὰρ ὑμῖν ὁ δῆμος ἐν ἁπάσαις ταῖς πόλεσιν
εὔνους ἐστὶ, καὶ ἢ οὐ ξυναφίσταται τοῖς ὀλίγοις, ἢ ἐὰν βιασθῇ, ὑπάρχει τοῖς
ἀποστήσασι πολέμιος εὐθὺς, etc.

[69] See the striking observations of Thucydidês, iii, 82, 83; Aristotel. Politic.
v, 6, 9.

[70] Thucyd. iii, 27.

[71] Thucyd. viii, 9-14. He observes, also, respecting the Thasian oligarchy
just set up in lieu of the previous democracy by the Athenian oligarchical
conspirators who were then organizing the revolution of the Four Hundred at
Athens,—that they immediately made preparations for revolting from Athens,—
ξυνέβη οὖν αὐτοῖς μάλιστα ἃ ἐβούλοντο, τὴν πόλιν τε ἀκινδύνως ὀρθοῦσθαι, καὶ
τ ὸ ν ἐ ν α ν τ ι ω σ ό μ ε ν ο ν δ ῆ μ ο ν κ α τ α λ ε λ ύ σ θ α ι (viii, 64).

[72] Thucyd. iv, 86, 88, 106, 123.

[73] See the important passage, Thucyd. viii, 48.

[74] Xenophon. Repub. Athen. iii, 5. πλὴν αἱ τάξεις τοῦ φόρου· τοῦτο δὲ
γίγνεται ὡς τὰ πολλὰ δι᾽ ἔτους πέμπτου.

[75] Xenophon. Repub. Athen. i, 14. Περὶ δὲ τῶν συμμάχων, οἱ ἐκπλέοντες


συκοφαντοῦσιν, ὡς δοκοῦσι, καὶ μισοῦσι τοὺς χρηστοὺς, etc.
Welcome to our website – the perfect destination for book lovers and
knowledge seekers. We believe that every book holds a new world,
offering opportunities for learning, discovery, and personal growth.
That’s why we are dedicated to bringing you a diverse collection of
books, ranging from classic literature and specialized publications to
self-development guides and children's books.

More than just a book-buying platform, we strive to be a bridge


connecting you with timeless cultural and intellectual values. With an
elegant, user-friendly interface and a smart search system, you can
quickly find the books that best suit your interests. Additionally,
our special promotions and home delivery services help you save time
and fully enjoy the joy of reading.

Join us on a journey of knowledge exploration, passion nurturing, and


personal growth every day!

testbankdeal.com

You might also like