(eBook PDF) A Concise Introduction to Ethicspdf download
(eBook PDF) A Concise Introduction to Ethicspdf download
download
https://ebookluna.com/product/ebook-pdf-a-concise-introduction-
to-ethics/
https://ebookluna.com/product/ebook-pdf-a-concise-introduction-to-
logic-13th-edition/
https://ebookluna.com/product/ebook-pdf-a-concise-introduction-to-
linguistics-5th-edition/
https://ebookluna.com/product/ebook-pdf-a-concise-introduction-to-world-
religion-3rd-edition/
https://ebookluna.com/product/ebook-pdf-a-concise-introduction-to-world-
religions-4th-edition/
(eBook PDF) Weather: A Concise Introduction
https://ebookluna.com/product/ebook-pdf-weather-a-concise-introduction/
https://ebookluna.com/download/a-concise-introduction-to-logic-14th-
edition-ebook-pdf/
https://ebookluna.com/product/original-pdf-canadian-democracy-a-concise-
introduction/
https://ebookluna.com/product/ebook-pdf-mirror-for-humanity-a-concise-
introduction-to-cultural-anthropology-12th-edition/
https://ebookluna.com/product/ebook-pdf-psychology-a-concise-
introduction-5th-edition/
A Concise Introduction to Ethics
A Concise Introduction to Ethics
RUSS SHAFER-LANDAU
UNIVERSITY OF WISCONSIN AT MADISON
Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the
University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing
worldwide. Oxford is a registered trademark of Oxford University Press in the UK and
certain other countries.
For titles covered by Section 112 of the US Higher Education Opportunity Act, please
visit www.oup.com/us/he for the latest information about pricing and alternate formats.
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval
system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission in
writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, by license, or under
terms agreed with the appropriate reproduction rights organization. Inquiries concerning
reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department,
Oxford University Press, at the address above.
You must not circulate this work in any other form and you must impose this same
condition on any acquirer.
987654321
Printed by LSC Communications, United States of America
CONTENTS
Preface
CHAPTER 6. Consequentialism
A. The Nature of Consequentialism
B. The Attractions of Utilitarianism
C. Some Difficulties for Utilitarianism
D. Conclusion
Key Terms and Concepts
Discussion Questions
Cases for Critical Reflection
Acknowledgments
As always, Robert Miller has been a dream editor to work with; his assistant
at OUP, Sydney Keen, has been an absolute delight, capable in every way.
I’d also like to express my gratitude to the fine philosophers who offered
needed guidance and such constructive criticism when reviewing the
manuscript:
Luke Amentas, St. Johns University
Robert Farley, Hillsborough Community College
Bob Fischer, Texas State
Theodore Gracyk, Minnesota State
Max Latona, Anselm College
Philip Robbins, University of Missouri
My aim for this book is to give a lot of bang for the buck, conveying
much of what is essential to moral philosophy in a compact and accessible
way. I’m sure I haven’t always hit the target. If you have ideas for how this
book might be improved, please let me know: russshaferlandau@gmail.com.
Not for Profit. All for Education.
Oxford University Press USA is a not-for-profit publisher dedicated to
offering the highest quality textbooks at the best possible prices. We
believe that it is important to provide everyone with access to superior
textbooks at affordable prices. Oxford University Press textbooks are
30%–70% less expensive than comparable books from commercial
publishers.
What Is Morality?
B be useful to first have some idea of what you are getting yourself into.
One way—sometimes the best—to gain such an understanding is by
considering a definition. When you open your trigonometry text or chemistry
handbook, you’ll likely be given, very early on, a definition of the area you
are about to study. So, as a responsible author, I would seem to have a duty
now to present you with a definition of morality.
I’d certainly like to. But I can’t. There is no widely agreed-on definition
of morality. The absence of a definition does not leave us entirely in the dark,
however. (After all, no one has yet been able to offer informative definitions
of literature, or life, or art, and yet we know a great deal about those things.)
Indeed, we can get a good sense of our subject matter by doing these four
things:
1. Being clear about the difference between conventional and critical
morality
2. Distinguishing the different branches of moral philosophy and their
central questions
3. Identifying starting points for moral thinking
4. Contrasting morality with other systems of guidance, including
religious ones
Let’s get to work!
A. Conventional and Critical Morality
Suppose you take a sociology or an anthropology course, and you get to a
unit on the morality of the cultures you’ve been studying. You’ll likely focus
on the patterns of behavior to be found in the cultures, their accepted ideas
about right and wrong, and the sorts of character traits that these cultures find
admirable. These are the elements of what we can call conventional
morality—the system of widely accepted rules and principles, created by and
for human beings, that members of a culture or society use to govern their
own lives and to assess the actions and the motivations of others. The
elements of conventional morality can be known by any astute social
observer, since gaining such knowledge is a matter of appreciating what most
people in a society or culture actually take to be right or wrong.
Conventional morality can differ from society to society. The
conventional morality of Saudi Arabia forbids women from publicly
contradicting their husbands or brothers, while Denmark’s conventional
morality allows this. People in the United States would think it immoral to
leave a restaurant without tipping a good waiter or bartender, while such
behavior in many other societies is perfectly OK.
When I write about morality in this book, I am not referring to
conventional morality. I am assuming that some social standards—even those
that are long-standing and very popular—can be morally mistaken. (We’ll
examine this assumption in Chapter 3.B.) After all, the set of traditional
principles that are widely shared within a culture or society are the result of
human decisions, agreements, and practices, all of which are sometimes
based on misunderstandings, irrationality, bias, or superstition. So when I talk
about morality from this point on, I will be referring to moral standards that
are not rooted in widespread endorsement, but rather are independent of
conventional morality and can be used to critically evaluate its merits.
It’s possible, of course, that conventional morality is all there is. But this
would be a very surprising discovery. Most of us assume, as I will do, that
the popularity of a moral view is not a guarantee of its truth. We could be
wrong on this point, but until we have a chance to consider the matter in
detail, I think it best to assume that conventional morality can sometimes be
mistaken. If so, then there may be some independent, critical morality that
(1) does not have its origin in social agreements; (2) is untainted by mistaken
beliefs, irrationality, or popular prejudices; and (3) can serve as the true
standard for determining when conventional morality has got it right and
when it has fallen into error. That is the morality whose nature we are going
to explore in this book.
Our website is not just a platform for buying books, but a bridge
connecting readers to the timeless values of culture and wisdom. With
an elegant, user-friendly interface and an intelligent search system,
we are committed to providing a quick and convenient shopping
experience. Additionally, our special promotions and home delivery
services ensure that you save time and fully enjoy the joy of reading.
ebookluna.com